The 6 Most Important Theories of Teaching

Tom Werner / Getty Images

  • An Introduction to Teaching
  • Tips & Strategies
  • Policies & Discipline
  • Community Involvement
  • School Administration
  • Technology in the Classroom
  • Teaching Adult Learners
  • Issues In Education
  • Teaching Resources
  • Becoming A Teacher
  • Assessments & Tests
  • Elementary Education
  • Secondary Education
  • Special Education
  • Homeschooling
  • M.A., Communications and Information Management, Bay Path College
  • B.A., Journalism and Design, Mount Holyoke College

The learning process has been a popular subject for theoretical analysis for decades. While some of those theories never leave the abstract realm, many of them are put into practice in classrooms on a daily basis. Teachers synthesize multiple theories, some of them decades-old, in order to improve their students' learning outcomes. The following theories of teaching represent some of the most popular and well-known in the field of education.

Multiple Intelligences

The theory of multiple intelligences , developed by Howard Gardner, posits that humans can possess eight different types of intelligence: musical-rhythmic, visual-spatial, verbal-linguistic, bodily-kinesthetic, interpersonal, intrapersonal, and naturalistic. These eight types of intelligence represent the varied ways individuals process information. 

The theory of multiple intelligence transformed the world of learning and pedagogy. Today, many teachers employ curriculums that have been developed around eight types of intelligence. Lessons are designed to include techniques that align with each individual student's learning style.

Bloom's Taxonomy

Developed in 1956 by Benjamin Bloom, Bloom’s Taxonomy is a hierarchical model of learning objectives. The model organizes individual educational tasks, such as comparing concepts and defining words, into six distinct educational categories: knowledge, comprehension, application, analysis, synthesis, and evaluation. The six categories are organized in order of complexity.

Bloom's Taxonomy gives educators a common language to communicate about learning and helps teachers establish clear learning goals for students. However, some critics contend that the taxonomy imposes an artificial sequence on learning and overlooks some crucial classroom concepts, such as behavior management. 

Zone of Proximal Development (ZPD) and Scaffolding

Lev Vygotsky developed a number of important pedagogical theories, but two of his most important classroom concepts are the Zone of Proximal Development and scaffolding .

According to Vygotsky, the Zone of Proximal Development (ZPD) is the conceptual gap between what a student is  and is   not  able to accomplish independently. Vygotsky suggested that the best way for teachers to support their students is by identifying the Zone of Proximal Development and working with them to accomplish tasks just beyond it. For example, a teacher might choose a challenging short story, just outside of what would be easily digestible for the students, for an in-class reading assignment. The teacher would then provide support and encouragement for the students to hone their reading comprehension skills throughout the lesson.

The second theory, scaffolding, is the act of adjusting the level of support provided in order to best meet each child's abilities. For example, when teaching a new math concept, a teacher would first walk the student through each step to complete the task. As the student begins to gain an understanding of the concept, the teacher would gradually reduce the support, moving away from step-by-step direction in favor of nudges and reminders until the student could complete the task entirely on her own.

Schema and Constructivism

Jean Piaget's schema theory suggests new knowledge with students' existing knowledge, the students will gain a deeper understanding of the new topic. This theory invites teachers to consider what their students already know before starting a lesson. This theory plays out in many classrooms every day when teachers begin lessons by asking their students what they already know about a particular concept. 

Piaget's theory of constructivism, which states that individuals construct meaning through action and experience, plays a major role in schools today. A constructivist classroom is one in which students learn by doing, rather than by passively absorbing knowledge. Constructivism plays out in many early childhood education programs, where children spend their days engaged in hands-on activities.

Behaviorism

Behaviorism, a set of theories laid out by B.F. Skinner, suggests that all behavior is a response to an external stimulus. In the classroom, behaviorism is the theory that students' learning and behavior will improve in response to positive reinforcement like rewards, praise, and bonuses. The behaviorist theory also asserts that negative reinforcement — in other words, punishment — will cause a child to stop undesired behavior. According to Skinner, these repeated reinforcement techniques can  shape behavior and produce improves learning outcomes.

The theory of behaviorism is frequently criticized for failing to consider students' internal mental states as well as for sometimes creating the appearance of bribery or coercion.  

Spiral Curriculum

In the theory of the spiral curriculum, Jerome Bruner contends that children are capable of comprehending surprisingly challenging topics and issues, provided that they are presented in an age-appropriate manner. Bruner suggests that teachers revisit topics annually (hence the spiral image), adding complexity and nuance every year. Achieving a spiral curriculum requires an institutional approach to education, in which the teachers at a school coordinate their curriculums and set long-term, multi-year learning goals for their students. 

  • What Is the Zone of Proximal Development? Definition and Examples
  • Gradual Release of Responsibility Creates Independent Learners
  • Understanding Howard Gardner's Theory of Multiple Intelligence
  • Bloom's Taxonomy in the Classroom
  • Curriculum Mapping: Definition, Purpose, and Tips
  • 7 Buzzwords You're Most Likely to Hear in Education
  • A Comprehensive Review of the Star Reading Program
  • Curriculum Design: Definition, Purpose and Types
  • Multiple Intelligences in the ESL Classroom
  • A Review of Accelerated Reader
  • How Scaffolding Instruction Can Improve Comprehension
  • Multiple Intelligence Activities
  • Higher-Order Thinking Skills (HOTS) in Education
  • An Overview of Early Childhood Education
  • Teaching Students Who Have Musical Intelligence
  • Understanding the Meaning of Bodily-Kinesthetic Intelligence

Critical Theories of Education: An Introduction

  • First Online: 14 September 2022

Cite this chapter

Book cover

  • Greg William Misiaszek 4 ,
  • Janna M. Popoff 5 &
  • Ali A. Abdi 6  

1300 Accesses

2 Citations

This chapter gives an overall introduction to critical theories essential to education, as we lay out the histories, reasoning, needs, and overall structure of the Palgrave Handbook on Critical Theories of Education . We discuss the five groundings that are the conceptual and theoretical thematic constructions of the book as follows: praxis-oriented, fluidity, radical, utopic with countless possible future s , and using bottom-up approaches. We give our own brief summaries of the chapters within the following book’s parts: general critical theoretical perspectives and philosophies of education, critical race theories of education, critical international/global citizenship education, critical pedagogy/critical literacy studies in education, critical media/information studies and education, critical community-engaged learning/research, critical perspectives on science and mathematics education, critical gender/feminist studies in education, and critical Indigenous and Southern epistemologies of education.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
  • Durable hardcover edition

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Abdi, A. A. (2008). Europe and African thought systems and philosophies of education: ‘Re-culturing’ the trans-temporal discourses. Cultural Studies, 22 (2), 309–327. https://doi.org/10.1080/09502380701789216

Article   Google Scholar  

Abdi, A. A. (2020). Decolonizing knowledge, education and social development: Africanist perspectives. Beijing International Review of Education, 2 (4), 503–518. https://doi.org/10.1163/25902539-02040006

Achebe, C. (2000). Home and exile . Oxford University Press.

Google Scholar  

Adorno, T. W. (1998). Education after Auschwitz. In T. W. Adorno (Ed.), Critical models: Interventions and catchwords (pp. 177–190). Columbia University Press.

Battiste, M. (1998). Enabling the autumn seed: Toward a decolonized approach to aboriginal knowledge, language, and education. Canadian Journal of Native Education, 22 (1), 16–27.

Dolby, N., Dimitriadis, G., & Willis, P. E. (2004). Learning to labor in new times . RoutledgeFalmer.

Freire, P. (1992). Pedagogy of hope . Continuum.

Freire, P. (1993). Pedagogy of the city . Continuum.

Freire, P. (1998). Pedagogy of freedom: Ethics, democracy, and civic courage . Rowman & Littlefield.

Freire, P. (2000). Pedagogy of the oppressed . Continuum.

Freire, P. (2004). Pedagogy of indignation . Paradigm Publishers.

Freire, P. (2005). Pedagogy of the oppressed . Continuum.

Gadotti, M. (1996). Pedagogy of praxis: A dialectical philosophy of education . SUNY Press.

Gadotti, M. (2008). Education for sustainable development: What we need to learn to save the planet . São Paulo: Instituto Paulo Freire.

Held, D., & McGrew, A. G. (2003). The global transformations reader: An introduction to the globalization debate (2nd ed.). Polity Press

Illich, I. (1983). Deschooling society (1st Harper Colophon ed.). New York: Harper Colophon.

Memmi, A. (1991). The colonizer and the colonized (Expanded ed.). Beacon Press.

Misiaszek, G. W. (2020). Ecopedagogy: Critical environmental teaching for planetary justice and global sustainable development . Bloomsbury.

Book   Google Scholar  

Morales-Doyle, D., & Gutstein, E. R. (2019). Racial capitalism and STEM education in Chicago Public Schools. Race Ethnicity and Education, 22 (4), 525–544. https://doi.org/10.1080/13613324.2019.1592840

Morrow, R. A. (2019). Paulo Freire and the “logic of reinvention”: Power, the State, and education in the global age. In C. A. Torres (Ed.), Wiley handbook of Paulo Freire (pp. 445–462). Wiley-Blackwell.

Morrow, R. A., & Torres, C. A. (2019). Rereading Freire and Habermas: Philosophical anthropology and reframing critical pedagogy and educational research in the neoliberal anthropocene. In C. A. Torres (Ed.), Wiley handbook of Paulo Freire (pp. 241–274). Wiley-Blackwell.

Nyerere, J. K. (1968). Freedom and socialism. Uhuru na ujamaa; a selection from writings and speeches, 1965–1967 . Oxford University Press.

Peters, M. A., Rider, S., Hyvönen, M., & Besley, T. (2018). Post-truth, fake news: Viral modernity & higher education . Springer.

Pongratz, L. (2005). Critical theory and pedagogy: Theodor W. Adorno and Max Horkheimer’s contemporary significance for a critical pedagogy. In G. Fischman, P. McLaren, H. Sunker, & C. Lankshear (Eds.), Critical theories, radical pedagogies, and global conflicts (pp. 154–163). Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.

Rodney, W. (1981). How Europe underdeveloped Africa (Rev). Howard University Press.

Said, E. W. (1979). Orientalism . Vintage Books.

Salamon, G. (2018). What’s critical about phenomenology? Pucta: Journal of Critical Phenomenology, 1 (1), 8–17. Retrieved from http://journals.oregondigital.org/index.php/pjcp/article/view/PJCP.v1i1.2

Santos, B. d. S. (2007). Beyond abyssal thinking: From global lines to ecologies of knowledges. Review (Fernand Braudel Center), 30 (1), 45–89. Retrieved from http://www.jstor.org/stable/40241677

Santos, B. d. S. (2014). Epistemologies of the South: Justice against epistemicide . Paradigm Publishers

Santos, B. d. S. (2018). The end of the cognitive empire: The coming of age of epistemologies of the South . Duke University Press.

Sifuna, D. N., & Otiende, J. E. (2006). An introductory history of education . Nairobi University Press.

Sontag, S. (1977). On photography . Dell Publishing Co.

Stromquist, N. P., & Monkman, K. (2002). Globalization and education: Integration and contestation across cultures . Rowman & Littlefield.

Taylor, A. (2017). Beyond stewardship: Common world pedagogies for the Anthropocene. Environmental Education Research, 23 (10), 1448–1461. https://doi.org/10.1080/13504622.2017.1325452

Torres, C. A. (2009). Globalizations and education: Collected essays on class, race, gender, and the state . Teachers College Press.

Willis, P. E. (1981). Learning to labor: How working class kids get working class jobs (Morningside). Columbia University Press.

Download references

Author information

Authors and affiliations.

Faculty of Education, Institute of Educational Theories, Beijing Normal University, Beijing, China

Greg William Misiaszek

Thompson Rivers University (TRU), Kamloops, BC, Canada

Janna M. Popoff

University of British Columbia (UBC), Vancouver, BC, Canada

Ali A. Abdi

You can also search for this author in PubMed   Google Scholar

Editor information

Editors and affiliations.

Department of Educational Studies, University of British Columbia, Vancouver, BC, Canada

Beijing Normal University, Beijing, China

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Misiaszek, G.W., Popoff, J.M., Abdi, A.A. (2022). Critical Theories of Education: An Introduction. In: Abdi, A.A., Misiaszek, G.W. (eds) The Palgrave Handbook on Critical Theories of Education. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-86343-2_1

Download citation

DOI : https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-86343-2_1

Published : 14 September 2022

Publisher Name : Palgrave Macmillan, Cham

Print ISBN : 978-3-030-86342-5

Online ISBN : 978-3-030-86343-2

eBook Packages : Education Education (R0)

Share this chapter

Anyone you share the following link with will be able to read this content:

Sorry, a shareable link is not currently available for this article.

Provided by the Springer Nature SharedIt content-sharing initiative

  • Publish with us

Policies and ethics

  • Find a journal
  • Track your research

SEP home page

  • Table of Contents
  • Random Entry
  • Chronological
  • Editorial Information
  • About the SEP
  • Editorial Board
  • How to Cite the SEP
  • Special Characters
  • Advanced Tools
  • Support the SEP
  • PDFs for SEP Friends
  • Make a Donation
  • SEPIA for Libraries
  • Entry Contents

Bibliography

Academic tools.

  • Friends PDF Preview
  • Author and Citation Info
  • Back to Top

Philosophy of Education

Philosophy of education is the branch of applied or practical philosophy concerned with the nature and aims of education and the philosophical problems arising from educational theory and practice. Because that practice is ubiquitous in and across human societies, its social and individual manifestations so varied, and its influence so profound, the subject is wide-ranging, involving issues in ethics and social/political philosophy, epistemology, metaphysics, philosophy of mind and language, and other areas of philosophy. Because it looks both inward to the parent discipline and outward to educational practice and the social, legal, and institutional contexts in which it takes place, philosophy of education concerns itself with both sides of the traditional theory/practice divide. Its subject matter includes both basic philosophical issues (e.g., the nature of the knowledge worth teaching, the character of educational equality and justice, etc.) and problems concerning specific educational policies and practices (e.g., the desirability of standardized curricula and testing, the social, economic, legal and moral dimensions of specific funding arrangements, the justification of curriculum decisions, etc.). In all this the philosopher of education prizes conceptual clarity, argumentative rigor, the fair-minded consideration of the interests of all involved in or affected by educational efforts and arrangements, and informed and well-reasoned valuation of educational aims and interventions.

Philosophy of education has a long and distinguished history in the Western philosophical tradition, from Socrates’ battles with the sophists to the present day. Many of the most distinguished figures in that tradition incorporated educational concerns into their broader philosophical agendas (Curren 2000, 2018; Rorty 1998). While that history is not the focus here, it is worth noting that the ideals of reasoned inquiry championed by Socrates and his descendants have long informed the view that education should foster in all students, to the extent possible, the disposition to seek reasons and the ability to evaluate them cogently, and to be guided by their evaluations in matters of belief, action and judgment. This view, that education centrally involves the fostering of reason or rationality, has with varying articulations and qualifications been embraced by most of those historical figures; it continues to be defended by contemporary philosophers of education as well (Scheffler 1973 [1989]; Siegel 1988, 1997, 2007, 2017). As with any philosophical thesis it is controversial; some dimensions of the controversy are explored below.

This entry is a selective survey of important contemporary work in Anglophone philosophy of education; it does not treat in detail recent scholarship outside that context.

1. Problems in Delineating the Field

2. analytic philosophy of education and its influence, 3.1 the content of the curriculum and the aims and functions of schooling, 3.2 social, political and moral philosophy, 3.3 social epistemology, virtue epistemology, and the epistemology of education, 3.4 philosophical disputes concerning empirical education research, 4. concluding remarks, other internet resources, related entries.

The inward/outward looking nature of the field of philosophy of education alluded to above makes the task of delineating the field, of giving an over-all picture of the intellectual landscape, somewhat complicated (for a detailed account of this topography, see Phillips 1985, 2010). Suffice it to say that some philosophers, as well as focusing inward on the abstract philosophical issues that concern them, are drawn outwards to discuss or comment on issues that are more commonly regarded as falling within the purview of professional educators, educational researchers, policy-makers and the like. (An example is Michael Scriven, who in his early career was a prominent philosopher of science; later he became a central figure in the development of the field of evaluation of educational and social programs. See Scriven 1991a, 1991b.) At the same time, there are professionals in the educational or closely related spheres who are drawn to discuss one or another of the philosophical issues that they encounter in the course of their work. (An example here is the behaviorist psychologist B.F. Skinner, the central figure in the development of operant conditioning and programmed learning, who in works such as Walden Two (1948) and Beyond Freedom and Dignity (1972) grappled—albeit controversially—with major philosophical issues that were related to his work.)

What makes the field even more amorphous is the existence of works on educational topics, written by well-regarded philosophers who have made major contributions to their discipline; these educational reflections have little or no philosophical content, illustrating the truth that philosophers do not always write philosophy. However, despite this, works in this genre have often been treated as contributions to philosophy of education. (Examples include John Locke’s Some Thoughts Concerning Education [1693] and Bertrand Russell’s rollicking pieces written primarily to raise funds to support a progressive school he ran with his wife. (See Park 1965.)

Finally, as indicated earlier, the domain of education is vast, the issues it raises are almost overwhelmingly numerous and are of great complexity, and the social significance of the field is second to none. These features make the phenomena and problems of education of great interest to a wide range of socially-concerned intellectuals, who bring with them their own favored conceptual frameworks—concepts, theories and ideologies, methods of analysis and argumentation, metaphysical and other assumptions, and the like. It is not surprising that scholars who work in this broad genre also find a home in the field of philosophy of education.

As a result of these various factors, the significant intellectual and social trends of the past few centuries, together with the significant developments in philosophy, all have had an impact on the content of arguments and methods of argumentation in philosophy of education—Marxism, psycho-analysis, existentialism, phenomenology, positivism, post-modernism, pragmatism, neo-liberalism, the several waves of feminism, analytic philosophy in both its ordinary language and more formal guises, are merely the tip of the iceberg.

Conceptual analysis, careful assessment of arguments, the rooting out of ambiguity, the drawing of clarifying distinctions—all of which are at least part of the philosophical toolkit—have been respected activities within philosophy from the dawn of the field. No doubt it somewhat over-simplifies the complex path of intellectual history to suggest that what happened in the twentieth century—early on, in the home discipline itself, and with a lag of a decade or more in philosophy of education—is that philosophical analysis came to be viewed by some scholars as being the major philosophical activity (or set of activities), or even as being the only viable or reputable activity. In any case, as they gained prominence and for a time hegemonic influence during the rise of analytic philosophy early in the twentieth century analytic techniques came to dominate philosophy of education in the middle third of that century (Curren, Robertson, & Hager 2003).

The pioneering work in the modern period entirely in an analytic mode was the short monograph by C.D. Hardie, Truth and Fallacy in Educational Theory (1941; reissued in 1962). In his Introduction, Hardie (who had studied with C.D. Broad and I.A. Richards) made it clear that he was putting all his eggs into the ordinary-language-analysis basket:

The Cambridge analytical school, led by Moore, Broad and Wittgenstein, has attempted so to analyse propositions that it will always be apparent whether the disagreement between philosophers is one concerning matters of fact, or is one concerning the use of words, or is, as is frequently the case, a purely emotive one. It is time, I think, that a similar attitude became common in the field of educational theory. (Hardie 1962: xix)

About a decade after the end of the Second World War the floodgates opened and a stream of work in the analytic mode appeared; the following is merely a sample. D. J. O’Connor published An Introduction to Philosophy of Education (1957) in which, among other things, he argued that the word “theory” as it is used in educational contexts is merely a courtesy title, for educational theories are nothing like what bear this title in the natural sciences. Israel Scheffler, who became the paramount philosopher of education in North America, produced a number of important works including The Language of Education (1960), which contained clarifying and influential analyses of definitions (he distinguished reportive, stipulative, and programmatic types) and the logic of slogans (often these are literally meaningless, and, he argued, should be seen as truncated arguments), Conditions of Knowledge (1965), still the best introduction to the epistemological side of philosophy of education, and Reason and Teaching (1973 [1989]), which in a wide-ranging and influential series of essays makes the case for regarding the fostering of rationality/critical thinking as a fundamental educational ideal (cf. Siegel 2016). B. O. Smith and R. H. Ennis edited the volume Language and Concepts in Education (1961); and R.D. Archambault edited Philosophical Analysis and Education (1965), consisting of essays by a number of prominent British writers, most notably R. S. Peters (whose status in Britain paralleled that of Scheffler in the United States), Paul Hirst, and John Wilson. Topics covered in the Archambault volume were typical of those that became the “bread and butter” of analytic philosophy of education (APE) throughout the English-speaking world—education as a process of initiation, liberal education, the nature of knowledge, types of teaching, and instruction versus indoctrination.

Among the most influential products of APE was the analysis developed by Hirst and Peters (1970) and Peters (1973) of the concept of education itself. Using as a touchstone “normal English usage,” it was concluded that a person who has been educated (rather than instructed or indoctrinated) has been (i) changed for the better; (ii) this change has involved the acquisition of knowledge and intellectual skills and the development of understanding; and (iii) the person has come to care for, or be committed to, the domains of knowledge and skill into which he or she has been initiated. The method used by Hirst and Peters comes across clearly in their handling of the analogy with the concept of “reform”, one they sometimes drew upon for expository purposes. A criminal who has been reformed has changed for the better, and has developed a commitment to the new mode of life (if one or other of these conditions does not hold, a speaker of standard English would not say the criminal has been reformed). Clearly the analogy with reform breaks down with respect to the knowledge and understanding conditions. Elsewhere Peters developed the fruitful notion of “education as initiation”.

The concept of indoctrination was also of great interest to analytic philosophers of education, for, it was argued, getting clear about precisely what constitutes indoctrination also would serve to clarify the border that demarcates it from acceptable educational processes. Thus, whether or not an instructional episode was a case of indoctrination was determined by the content taught, the intention of the instructor, the methods of instruction used, the outcomes of the instruction, or by some combination of these. Adherents of the different analyses used the same general type of argument to make their case, namely, appeal to normal and aberrant usage. Unfortunately, ordinary language analysis did not lead to unanimity of opinion about where this border was located, and rival analyses of the concept were put forward (Snook 1972). The danger of restricting analysis to ordinary language (“normal English usage”) was recognized early on by Scheffler, whose preferred view of analysis emphasized

first, its greater sophistication as regards language, and the interpenetration of language and inquiry, second, its attempt to follow the modern example of the sciences in empirical spirit, in rigor, in attention to detail, in respect for alternatives, and in objectivity of method, and third, its use of techniques of symbolic logic brought to full development only in the last fifty years… It is…this union of scientific spirit and logical method applied toward the clarification of basic ideas that characterizes current analytic philosophy [and that ought to characterize analytic philosophy of education]. (Scheffler 1973 [1989: 9–10])

After a period of dominance, for a number of important reasons the influence of APE went into decline. First, there were growing criticisms that the work of analytic philosophers of education had become focused upon minutiae and in the main was bereft of practical import. (It is worth noting that a 1966 article in Time , reprinted in Lucas 1969, had put forward the same criticism of mainstream philosophy.) Second, in the early 1970’s radical students in Britain accused Peters’ brand of linguistic analysis of conservatism, and of tacitly giving support to “traditional values”—they raised the issue of whose English usage was being analyzed?

Third, criticisms of language analysis in mainstream philosophy had been mounting for some time, and finally after a lag of many years were reaching the attention of philosophers of education; there even had been a surprising degree of interest on the part of the general reading public in the United Kingdom as early as 1959, when Gilbert Ryle, editor of the journal Mind , refused to commission a review of Ernest Gellner’s Words and Things (1959)—a detailed and quite acerbic critique of Wittgenstein’s philosophy and its espousal of ordinary language analysis. (Ryle argued that Gellner’s book was too insulting, a view that drew Bertrand Russell into the fray on Gellner’s side—in the daily press, no less; Russell produced a list of insulting remarks drawn from the work of great philosophers of the past. See Mehta 1963.)

Richard Peters had been given warning that all was not well with APE at a conference in Canada in 1966; after delivering a paper on “The aims of education: A conceptual inquiry” that was based on ordinary language analysis, a philosopher in the audience (William Dray) asked Peters “ whose concepts do we analyze?” Dray went on to suggest that different people, and different groups within society, have different concepts of education. Five years before the radical students raised the same issue, Dray pointed to the possibility that what Peters had presented under the guise of a “logical analysis” was nothing but the favored usage of a certain class of persons—a class that Peters happened to identify with (see Peters 1973, where to the editor’s credit the interaction with Dray is reprinted).

Fourth, during the decade of the seventies when these various critiques of analytic philosophy were in the process of eroding its luster, a spate of translations from the Continent stimulated some philosophers of education in Britain and North America to set out in new directions, and to adopt a new style of writing and argumentation. Key works by Gadamer, Foucault and Derrida appeared in English, and these were followed in 1984 by Lyotard’s The Postmodern Condition . The classic works of Heidegger and Husserl also found new admirers; and feminist philosophers of education were finding their voices—Maxine Greene published a number of pieces in the 1970s and 1980s, including The Dialectic of Freedom (1988); the influential book by Nel Noddings, Caring: A Feminine Approach to Ethics and Moral Education , appeared the same year as the work by Lyotard, followed a year later by Jane Roland Martin’s Reclaiming a Conversation . In more recent years all these trends have continued. APE was and is no longer the center of interest, although, as indicated below, it still retains its voice.

3. Areas of Contemporary Activity

As was stressed at the outset, the field of education is huge and contains within it a virtually inexhaustible number of issues that are of philosophical interest. To attempt comprehensive coverage of how philosophers of education have been working within this thicket would be a quixotic task for a large single volume and is out of the question for a solitary encyclopedia entry. Nevertheless, a valiant attempt to give an overview was made in A Companion to the Philosophy of Education (Curren 2003), which contains more than six-hundred pages divided into forty-five chapters each of which surveys a subfield of work. The following random selection of chapter topics gives a sense of the enormous scope of the field: Sex education, special education, science education, aesthetic education, theories of teaching and learning, religious education, knowledge, truth and learning, cultivating reason, the measurement of learning, multicultural education, education and the politics of identity, education and standards of living, motivation and classroom management, feminism, critical theory, postmodernism, romanticism, the purposes of universities, affirmative action in higher education, and professional education. The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Education (Siegel 2009) contains a similarly broad range of articles on (among other things) the epistemic and moral aims of education, liberal education and its imminent demise, thinking and reasoning, fallibilism and fallibility, indoctrination, authenticity, the development of rationality, Socratic teaching, educating the imagination, caring and empathy in moral education, the limits of moral education, the cultivation of character, values education, curriculum and the value of knowledge, education and democracy, art and education, science education and religious toleration, constructivism and scientific methods, multicultural education, prejudice, authority and the interests of children, and on pragmatist, feminist, and postmodernist approaches to philosophy of education.

Given this enormous range, there is no non-arbitrary way to select a small number of topics for further discussion, nor can the topics that are chosen be pursued in great depth. The choice of those below has been made with an eye to highlighting contemporary work that makes solid contact with and contributes to important discussions in general philosophy and/or the academic educational and educational research communities.

The issue of what should be taught to students at all levels of education—the issue of curriculum content—obviously is a fundamental one, and it is an extraordinarily difficult one with which to grapple. In tackling it, care needs to be taken to distinguish between education and schooling—for although education can occur in schools, so can mis-education, and many other things can take place there that are educationally orthogonal (such as the provision of free or subsidized lunches and the development of social networks); and it also must be recognized that education can occur in the home, in libraries and museums, in churches and clubs, in solitary interaction with the public media, and the like.

In developing a curriculum (whether in a specific subject area, or more broadly as the whole range of offerings in an educational institution or system), a number of difficult decisions need to be made. Issues such as the proper ordering or sequencing of topics in the chosen subject, the time to be allocated to each topic, the lab work or excursions or projects that are appropriate for particular topics, can all be regarded as technical issues best resolved either by educationists who have a depth of experience with the target age group or by experts in the psychology of learning and the like. But there are deeper issues, ones concerning the validity of the justifications that have been given for including/excluding particular subjects or topics in the offerings of formal educational institutions. (Why should evolution or creation “science” be included, or excluded, as a topic within the standard high school subject Biology? Is the justification that is given for teaching Economics in some schools coherent and convincing? Do the justifications for including/excluding materials on birth control, patriotism, the Holocaust or wartime atrocities in the curriculum in some school districts stand up to critical scrutiny?)

The different justifications for particular items of curriculum content that have been put forward by philosophers and others since Plato’s pioneering efforts all draw, explicitly or implicitly, upon the positions that the respective theorists hold about at least three sets of issues.

First, what are the aims and/or functions of education (aims and functions are not necessarily the same)? Many aims have been proposed; a short list includes the production of knowledge and knowledgeable students, the fostering of curiosity and inquisitiveness, the enhancement of understanding, the enlargement of the imagination, the civilizing of students, the fostering of rationality and/or autonomy, and the development in students of care, concern and associated dispositions and attitudes (see Siegel 2007 for a longer list). The justifications offered for all such aims have been controversial, and alternative justifications of a single proposed aim can provoke philosophical controversy. Consider the aim of autonomy. Aristotle asked, what constitutes the good life and/or human flourishing, such that education should foster these (Curren 2013)? These two formulations are related, for it is arguable that our educational institutions should aim to equip individuals to pursue this good life—although this is not obvious, both because it is not clear that there is one conception of the good or flourishing life that is the good or flourishing life for everyone, and it is not clear that this is a question that should be settled in advance rather than determined by students for themselves. Thus, for example, if our view of human flourishing includes the capacity to think and act autonomously, then the case can be made that educational institutions—and their curricula—should aim to prepare, or help to prepare, autonomous individuals. A rival justification of the aim of autonomy, associated with Kant, champions the educational fostering of autonomy not on the basis of its contribution to human flourishing, but rather the obligation to treat students with respect as persons (Scheffler 1973 [1989]; Siegel 1988). Still others urge the fostering of autonomy on the basis of students’ fundamental interests, in ways that draw upon both Aristotelian and Kantian conceptual resources (Brighouse 2005, 2009). It is also possible to reject the fostering of autonomy as an educational aim (Hand 2006).

Assuming that the aim can be justified, how students should be helped to become autonomous or develop a conception of the good life and pursue it is of course not immediately obvious, and much philosophical ink has been spilled on the general question of how best to determine curriculum content. One influential line of argument was developed by Paul Hirst, who argued that knowledge is essential for developing and then pursuing a conception of the good life, and because logical analysis shows, he argued, that there are seven basic forms of knowledge, the case can be made that the function of the curriculum is to introduce students to each of these forms (Hirst 1965; see Phillips 1987: ch. 11). Another, suggested by Scheffler, is that curriculum content should be selected so as “to help the learner attain maximum self-sufficiency as economically as possible.” The relevant sorts of economy include those of resources, teacher effort, student effort, and the generalizability or transfer value of content, while the self-sufficiency in question includes

self-awareness, imaginative weighing of alternative courses of action, understanding of other people’s choices and ways of life, decisiveness without rigidity, emancipation from stereotyped ways of thinking and perceiving…empathy… intuition, criticism and independent judgment. (Scheffler 1973 [1989: 123–5])

Both impose important constraints on the curricular content to be taught.

Second, is it justifiable to treat the curriculum of an educational institution as a vehicle for furthering the socio-political interests and goals of a dominant group, or any particular group, including one’s own; and relatedly, is it justifiable to design the curriculum so that it serves as an instrument of control or of social engineering? In the closing decades of the twentieth century there were numerous discussions of curriculum theory, particularly from Marxist and postmodern perspectives, that offered the sobering analysis that in many educational systems, including those in Western democracies, the curriculum did indeed reflect and serve the interests of powerful cultural elites. What to do about this situation (if it is indeed the situation of contemporary educational institutions) is far from clear and is the focus of much work at the interface of philosophy of education and social/political philosophy, some of which is discussed in the next section. A closely related question is this: ought educational institutions be designed to further pre-determined social ends, or rather to enable students to competently evaluate all such ends? Scheffler argued that we should opt for the latter: we must

surrender the idea of shaping or molding the mind of the pupil. The function of education…is rather to liberate the mind, strengthen its critical powers, [and] inform it with knowledge and the capacity for independent inquiry. (Scheffler 1973 [1989: 139])

Third, should educational programs at the elementary and secondary levels be made up of a number of disparate offerings, so that individuals with different interests and abilities and affinities for learning can pursue curricula that are suitable? Or should every student pursue the same curriculum as far as each is able?—a curriculum, it should be noted, that in past cases nearly always was based on the needs or interests of those students who were academically inclined or were destined for elite social roles. Mortimer Adler and others in the late twentieth century sometimes used the aphorism “the best education for the best is the best education for all.”

The thinking here can be explicated in terms of the analogy of an out-of-control virulent disease, for which there is only one type of medicine available; taking a large dose of this medicine is extremely beneficial, and the hope is that taking only a little—while less effective—is better than taking none at all. Medically, this is dubious, while the educational version—forcing students to work, until they exit the system, on topics that do not interest them and for which they have no facility or motivation—has even less merit. (For a critique of Adler and his Paideia Proposal , see Noddings 2015.) It is interesting to compare the modern “one curriculum track for all” position with Plato’s system outlined in the Republic , according to which all students—and importantly this included girls—set out on the same course of study. Over time, as they moved up the educational ladder it would become obvious that some had reached the limit imposed upon them by nature, and they would be directed off into appropriate social roles in which they would find fulfillment, for their abilities would match the demands of these roles. Those who continued on with their education would eventually become members of the ruling class of Guardians.

The publication of John Rawls’s A Theory of Justice in 1971 was the most notable event in the history of political philosophy over the last century. The book spurred a period of ferment in political philosophy that included, among other things, new research on educationally fundamental themes. The principles of justice in educational distribution have perhaps been the dominant theme in this literature, and Rawls’s influence on its development has been pervasive.

Rawls’s theory of justice made so-called “fair equality of opportunity” one of its constitutive principles. Fair equality of opportunity entailed that the distribution of education would not put the children of those who currently occupied coveted social positions at any competitive advantage over other, equally talented and motivated children seeking the qualifications for those positions (Rawls 1971: 72–75). Its purpose was to prevent socio-economic differences from hardening into social castes that were perpetuated across generations. One obvious criticism of fair equality of opportunity is that it does not prohibit an educational distribution that lavished resources on the most talented children while offering minimal opportunities to others. So long as untalented students from wealthy families were assigned opportunities no better than those available to their untalented peers among the poor, no breach of the principle would occur. Even the most moderate egalitarians might find such a distributive regime to be intuitively repugnant.

Repugnance might be mitigated somewhat by the ways in which the overall structure of Rawls’s conception of justice protects the interests of those who fare badly in educational competition. All citizens must enjoy the same basic liberties, and equal liberty always has moral priority over equal opportunity: the former can never be compromised to advance the latter. Further, inequality in the distribution of income and wealth are permitted only to the degree that it serves the interests of the least advantaged group in society. But even with these qualifications, fair equality of opportunity is arguably less than really fair to anyone. The fact that their education should secure ends other than access to the most selective social positions—ends such as artistic appreciation, the kind of self-knowledge that humanistic study can furnish, or civic virtue—is deemed irrelevant according to Rawls’s principle. But surely it is relevant, given that a principle of educational justice must be responsive to the full range of educationally important goods.

Suppose we revise our account of the goods included in educational distribution so that aesthetic appreciation, say, and the necessary understanding and virtue for conscientious citizenship count for just as much as job-related skills. An interesting implication of doing so is that the rationale for requiring equality under any just distribution becomes decreasingly clear. That is because job-related skills are positional whereas the other educational goods are not (Hollis 1982). If you and I both aspire to a career in business management for which we are equally qualified, any increase in your job-related skills is a corresponding disadvantage to me unless I can catch up. Positional goods have a competitive structure by definition, though the ends of civic or aesthetic education do not fit that structure. If you and I aspire to be good citizens and are equal in civic understanding and virtue, an advance in your civic education is no disadvantage to me. On the contrary, it is easier to be a good citizen the better other citizens learn to be. At the very least, so far as non-positional goods figure in our conception of what counts as a good education, the moral stakes of inequality are thereby lowered.

In fact, an emerging alternative to fair equality of opportunity is a principle that stipulates some benchmark of adequacy in achievement or opportunity as the relevant standard of distribution. But it is misleading to represent this as a contrast between egalitarian and sufficientarian conceptions. Philosophically serious interpretations of adequacy derive from the ideal of equal citizenship (Satz 2007; Anderson 2007). Then again, fair equality of opportunity in Rawls’s theory is derived from a more fundamental ideal of equality among citizens. This was arguably true in A Theory of Justice but it is certainly true in his later work (Dworkin 1977: 150–183; Rawls 1993). So, both Rawls’s principle and the emerging alternative share an egalitarian foundation. The debate between adherents of equal opportunity and those misnamed as sufficientarians is certainly not over (e.g., Brighouse & Swift 2009; Jacobs 2010; Warnick 2015). Further progress will likely hinge on explicating the most compelling conception of the egalitarian foundation from which distributive principles are to be inferred. Another Rawls-inspired alternative is that a “prioritarian” distribution of achievement or opportunity might turn out to be the best principle we can come up with—i.e., one that favors the interests of the least advantaged students (Schouten 2012).

The publication of Rawls’s Political Liberalism in 1993 signaled a decisive turning point in his thinking about justice. In his earlier book, the theory of justice had been presented as if it were universally valid. But Rawls had come to think that any theory of justice presented as such was open to reasonable rejection. A more circumspect approach to justification would seek grounds for justice as fairness in an overlapping consensus between the many reasonable values and doctrines that thrive in a democratic political culture. Rawls argued that such a culture is informed by a shared ideal of free and equal citizenship that provided a new, distinctively democratic framework for justifying a conception of justice. The shift to political liberalism involved little revision on Rawls’s part to the content of the principles he favored. But the salience it gave to questions about citizenship in the fabric of liberal political theory had important educational implications. How was the ideal of free and equal citizenship to be instantiated in education in a way that accommodated the range of reasonable values and doctrines encompassed in an overlapping consensus? Political Liberalism has inspired a range of answers to that question (cf. Callan 1997; Clayton 2006; Bull 2008).

Other philosophers besides Rawls in the 1990s took up a cluster of questions about civic education, and not always from a liberal perspective. Alasdair Macintyre’s After Virtue (1984) strongly influenced the development of communitarian political theory which, as its very name might suggest, argued that the cultivation of community could preempt many of the problems with conflicting individual rights at the core of liberalism. As a full-standing alternative to liberalism, communitarianism might have little to recommend it. But it was a spur for liberal philosophers to think about how communities could be built and sustained to support the more familiar projects of liberal politics (e.g., Strike 2010). Furthermore, its arguments often converged with those advanced by feminist exponents of the ethic of care (Noddings 1984; Gilligan 1982). Noddings’ work is particularly notable because she inferred a cogent and radical agenda for the reform of schools from her conception of care (Noddings 1992).

One persistent controversy in citizenship theory has been about whether patriotism is correctly deemed a virtue, given our obligations to those who are not our fellow citizens in an increasingly interdependent world and the sordid history of xenophobia with which modern nation states are associated. The controversy is partly about what we should teach in our schools and is commonly discussed by philosophers in that context (Galston 1991; Ben-Porath 2006; Callan 2006; Miller 2007; Curren & Dorn 2018). The controversy is related to a deeper and more pervasive question about how morally or intellectually taxing the best conception of our citizenship should be. The more taxing it is, the more constraining its derivative conception of civic education will be. Contemporary political philosophers offer divergent arguments about these matters. For example, Gutmann and Thompson claim that citizens of diverse democracies need to “understand the diverse ways of life of their fellow citizens” (Gutmann & Thompson 1996: 66). The need arises from the obligation of reciprocity which they (like Rawls) believe to be integral to citizenship. Because I must seek to cooperate with others politically on terms that make sense from their moral perspective as well as my own, I must be ready to enter that perspective imaginatively so as to grasp its distinctive content. Many such perspectives prosper in liberal democracies, and so the task of reciprocal understanding is necessarily onerous. Still, our actions qua deliberative citizen must be grounded in such reciprocity if political cooperation on terms acceptable to us as (diversely) morally motivated citizens is to be possible at all. This is tantamount to an imperative to think autonomously inside the role of citizen because I cannot close-mindedly resist critical consideration of moral views alien to my own without flouting my responsibilities as a deliberative citizen.

Civic education does not exhaust the domain of moral education, even though the more robust conceptions of equal citizenship have far-reaching implications for just relations in civil society and the family. The study of moral education has traditionally taken its bearings from normative ethics rather than political philosophy, and this is largely true of work undertaken in recent decades. The major development here has been the revival of virtue ethics as an alternative to the deontological and consequentialist theories that dominated discussion for much of the twentieth century.

The defining idea of virtue ethics is that our criterion of moral right and wrong must derive from a conception of how the ideally virtuous agent would distinguish between the two. Virtue ethics is thus an alternative to both consequentialism and deontology which locate the relevant criterion in producing good consequences or meeting the requirements of moral duty respectively. The debate about the comparative merits of these theories is not resolved, but from an educational perspective that may be less important than it has sometimes seemed to antagonists in the debate. To be sure, adjudicating between rival theories in normative ethics might shed light on how best to construe the process of moral education, and philosophical reflection on the process might help us to adjudicate between the theories. There has been extensive work on habituation and virtue, largely inspired by Aristotle (Burnyeat 1980; Peters 1981). But whether this does anything to establish the superiority of virtue ethics over its competitors is far from obvious. Other aspects of moral education—in particular, the paired processes of role-modelling and identification—deserve much more scrutiny than they have received (Audi 2017; Kristjánsson 2015, 2017).

Related to the issues concerning the aims and functions of education and schooling rehearsed above are those involving the specifically epistemic aims of education and attendant issues treated by social and virtue epistemologists. (The papers collected in Kotzee 2013 and Baehr 2016 highlight the current and growing interactions among social epistemologists, virtue epistemologists, and philosophers of education.)

There is, first, a lively debate concerning putative epistemic aims. Alvin Goldman argues that truth (or knowledge understood in the “weak” sense of true belief) is the fundamental epistemic aim of education (Goldman 1999). Others, including the majority of historically significant philosophers of education, hold that critical thinking or rationality and rational belief (or knowledge in the “strong” sense that includes justification) is the basic epistemic educational aim (Bailin & Siegel 2003; Scheffler 1965, 1973 [1989]; Siegel 1988, 1997, 2005, 2017). Catherine Z. Elgin (1999a,b) and Duncan Pritchard (2013, 2016; Carter & Pritchard 2017) have independently urged that understanding is the basic aim. Pritchard’s view combines understanding with intellectual virtue ; Jason Baehr (2011) systematically defends the fostering of the intellectual virtues as the fundamental epistemic aim of education. This cluster of views continues to engender ongoing discussion and debate. (Its complex literature is collected in Carter and Kotzee 2015, summarized in Siegel 2018, and helpfully analyzed in Watson 2016.)

A further controversy concerns the places of testimony and trust in the classroom: In what circumstances if any ought students to trust their teachers’ pronouncements, and why? Here the epistemology of education is informed by social epistemology, specifically the epistemology of testimony; the familiar reductionism/anti-reductionism controversy there is applicable to students and teachers. Anti-reductionists, who regard testimony as a basic source of justification, may with equanimity approve of students’ taking their teachers’ word at face value and believing what they say; reductionists may balk. Does teacher testimony itself constitute good reason for student belief?

The correct answer here seems clearly enough to be “it depends”. For very young children who have yet to acquire or develop the ability to subject teacher declarations to critical scrutiny, there seems to be little alternative to accepting what their teachers tell them. For older and more cognitively sophisticated students there seem to be more options: they can assess them for plausibility, compare them with other opinions, assess the teachers’ proffered reasons, subject them to independent evaluation, etc. Regarding “the teacher says that p ” as itself a good reason to believe it appears moreover to contravene the widely shared conviction that an important educational aim is helping students to become able to evaluate candidate beliefs for themselves and believe accordingly. That said, all sides agree that sometimes believers, including students, have good reasons simply to trust what others tell them. There is thus more work to do here by both social epistemologists and philosophers of education (for further discussion see Goldberg 2013; Siegel 2005, 2018).

A further cluster of questions, of long-standing interest to philosophers of education, concerns indoctrination : How if at all does it differ from legitimate teaching? Is it inevitable, and if so is it not always necessarily bad? First, what is it? As we saw earlier, extant analyses focus on the aims or intentions of the indoctrinator, the methods employed, or the content transmitted. If the indoctrination is successful, all have the result that students/victims either don’t, won’t, or can’t subject the indoctrinated material to proper epistemic evaluation. In this way it produces both belief that is evidentially unsupported or contravened and uncritical dispositions to believe. It might seem obvious that indoctrination, so understood, is educationally undesirable. But it equally seems that very young children, at least, have no alternative but to believe sans evidence; they have yet to acquire the dispositions to seek and evaluate evidence, or the abilities to recognize evidence or evaluate it. Thus we seem driven to the views that indoctrination is both unavoidable and yet bad and to be avoided. It is not obvious how this conundrum is best handled. One option is to distinguish between acceptable and unacceptable indoctrination. Another is to distinguish between indoctrination (which is always bad) and non-indoctrinating belief inculcation, the latter being such that students are taught some things without reasons (the alphabet, the numbers, how to read and count, etc.), but in such a way that critical evaluation of all such material (and everything else) is prized and fostered (Siegel 1988: ch. 5). In the end the distinctions required by the two options might be extensionally equivalent (Siegel 2018).

Education, it is generally granted, fosters belief : in the typical propositional case, Smith teaches Jones that p , and if all goes well Jones learns it and comes to believe it. Education also has the task of fostering open-mindedness and an appreciation of our fallibility : All the theorists mentioned thus far, especially those in the critical thinking and intellectual virtue camps, urge their importance. But these two might seem at odds. If Jones (fully) believes that p , can she also be open-minded about it? Can she believe, for example, that earthquakes are caused by the movements of tectonic plates, while also believing that perhaps they aren’t? This cluster of italicized notions requires careful handling; it is helpfully discussed by Jonathan Adler (2002, 2003), who recommends regarding the latter two as meta-attitudes concerning one’s first-order beliefs rather than lessened degrees of belief or commitments to those beliefs.

Other traditional epistemological worries that impinge upon the epistemology of education concern (a) absolutism , pluralism and relativism with respect to knowledge, truth and justification as these relate to what is taught, (b) the character and status of group epistemologies and the prospects for understanding such epistemic goods “universalistically” in the face of “particularist” challenges, (c) the relation between “knowledge-how” and “knowledge-that” and their respective places in the curriculum, (d) concerns raised by multiculturalism and the inclusion/exclusion of marginalized perspectives in curriculum content and the classroom, and (e) further issues concerning teaching and learning. (There is more here than can be briefly summarized; for more references and systematic treatment cf. Bailin & Siegel 2003; Carter & Kotzee 2015; Cleverley & Phillips 1986; Robertson 2009; Siegel 2004, 2017; and Watson 2016.)

The educational research enterprise has been criticized for a century or more by politicians, policymakers, administrators, curriculum developers, teachers, philosophers of education, and by researchers themselves—but the criticisms have been contradictory. Charges of being “too ivory tower and theory-oriented” are found alongside “too focused on practice and too atheoretical”; but in light of the views of John Dewey and William James that the function of theory is to guide intelligent practice and problem-solving, it is becoming more fashionable to hold that the “theory v. practice” dichotomy is a false one. (For an illuminating account of the historical development of educational research and its tribulations, see Lagemann 2000.)

A similar trend can be discerned with respect to the long warfare between two rival groups of research methods—on one hand quantitative/statistical approaches to research, and on the other hand the qualitative/ethnographic family. (The choice of labels here is not entirely risk-free, for they have been contested; furthermore the first approach is quite often associated with “experimental” studies, and the latter with “case studies”, but this is an over-simplification.) For several decades these two rival methodological camps were treated by researchers and a few philosophers of education as being rival paradigms (Kuhn’s ideas, albeit in a very loose form, have been influential in the field of educational research), and the dispute between them was commonly referred to as “the paradigm wars”. In essence the issue at stake was epistemological: members of the quantitative/experimental camp believed that only their methods could lead to well-warranted knowledge claims, especially about the causal factors at play in educational phenomena, and on the whole they regarded qualitative methods as lacking in rigor; on the other hand the adherents of qualitative/ethnographic approaches held that the other camp was too “positivistic” and was operating with an inadequate view of causation in human affairs—one that ignored the role of motives and reasons, possession of relevant background knowledge, awareness of cultural norms, and the like. Few if any commentators in the “paradigm wars” suggested that there was anything prohibiting the use of both approaches in the one research program—provided that if both were used, they were used only sequentially or in parallel, for they were underwritten by different epistemologies and hence could not be blended together. But recently the trend has been towards rapprochement, towards the view that the two methodological families are, in fact, compatible and are not at all like paradigms in the Kuhnian sense(s) of the term; the melding of the two approaches is often called “mixed methods research”, and it is growing in popularity. (For more detailed discussion of these “wars” see Howe 2003 and Phillips 2009.)

The most lively contemporary debates about education research, however, were set in motion around the turn of the millennium when the US Federal Government moved in the direction of funding only rigorously scientific educational research—the kind that could establish causal factors which could then guide the development of practically effective policies. (It was held that such a causal knowledge base was available for medical decision-making.) The definition of “rigorously scientific”, however, was decided by politicians and not by the research community, and it was given in terms of the use of a specific research method—the net effect being that the only research projects to receive Federal funding were those that carried out randomized controlled experiments or field trials (RFTs). It has become common over the last decade to refer to the RFT as the “gold standard” methodology.

The National Research Council (NRC)—an arm of the US National Academies of Science—issued a report, influenced by postpostivistic philosophy of science (NRC 2002), that argued that this criterion was far too narrow. Numerous essays have appeared subsequently that point out how the “gold standard” account of scientific rigor distorts the history of science, how the complex nature of the relation between evidence and policy-making has been distorted and made to appear overly simple (for instance the role of value-judgments in linking empirical findings to policy directives is often overlooked), and qualitative researchers have insisted upon the scientific nature of their work. Nevertheless, and possibly because it tried to be balanced and supported the use of RFTs in some research contexts, the NRC report has been the subject of symposia in four journals, where it has been supported by a few and attacked from a variety of philosophical fronts: Its authors were positivists, they erroneously believed that educational inquiry could be value neutral and that it could ignore the ways in which the exercise of power constrains the research process, they misunderstood the nature of educational phenomena, and so on. This cluster of issues continues to be debated by educational researchers and by philosophers of education and of science, and often involves basic topics in philosophy of science: the constitution of warranting evidence, the nature of theories and of confirmation and explanation, etc. Nancy Cartwright’s important recent work on causation, evidence, and evidence-based policy adds layers of both philosophical sophistication and real world practical analysis to the central issues just discussed (Cartwright & Hardie 2012, Cartwright 2013; cf. Kvernbekk 2015 for an overview of the controversies regarding evidence in the education and philosophy of education literatures).

As stressed earlier, it is impossible to do justice to the whole field of philosophy of education in a single encyclopedia entry. Different countries around the world have their own intellectual traditions and their own ways of institutionalizing philosophy of education in the academic universe, and no discussion of any of this appears in the present essay. But even in the Anglo-American world there is such a diversity of approaches that any author attempting to produce a synoptic account will quickly run into the borders of his or her competence. Clearly this has happened in the present case.

Fortunately, in the last thirty years or so resources have become available that significantly alleviate these problems. There has been a flood of encyclopedia entries, both on the field as a whole and also on many specific topics not well-covered in the present essay (see, as a sample, Burbules 1994; Chambliss 1996b; Curren 1998, 2018; Phillips 1985, 2010; Siegel 2007; Smeyers 1994), two “Encyclopedias” (Chambliss 1996a; Phillips 2014), a “Guide” (Blake, Smeyers, Smith, & Standish 2003), a “Companion” (Curren 2003), two “Handbooks” (Siegel 2009; Bailey, Barrow, Carr, & McCarthy 2010), a comprehensive anthology (Curren 2007), a dictionary of key concepts in the field (Winch & Gingell 1999), and a good textbook or two (Carr 2003; Noddings 2015). In addition there are numerous volumes both of reprinted selections and of specially commissioned essays on specific topics, some of which were given short shrift here (for another sampling see A. Rorty 1998, Stone 1994), and several international journals, including Theory and Research in Education , Journal of Philosophy of Education , Educational Theory , Studies in Philosophy and Education , and Educational Philosophy and Theory . Thus there is more than enough material available to keep the interested reader busy.

  • Adler, Jonathan E., 2002, Belief’s Own Ethics , Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • –––, 2003, “Knowledge, Truth and Learning”, in Curren 2003: 285–304. doi:10.1002/9780470996454.ch21
  • Anderson, Elizabeth, 2007, “Fair Opportunity in Education: A Democratic Equality Perspective”, Ethics , 117(4): 595–622. doi:10.1086/518806
  • Archambault, Reginald D. (ed.), 1965, Philosophical Analysis and Education , London: Routledge.
  • Audi, Robert, 2017, “Role Modelling and Reasons: Developmental and Normative Grounds of Moral Virtue”, Journal of Moral Philosophy , 14(6): 646–668. doi:10.1163/17455243-46810063
  • Baehr, Jason, 2011, The Inquiring Mind: On Intellectual Virtues and Virtue Epistemology , Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199604074.001.0001
  • ––– (ed.), 2016, Intellectual Virtues and Education: Essays in Applied Virtue Epistemology , New York: Routledge.
  • Bailey, Richard, Robin Barrow, David Carr, and Christine McCarthy (eds), 2010, The SAGE Handbook of the Philosophy of Education , Los Angeles: Sage. doi:10.4135/9781446200872
  • Bailin, Sharon and Harvey Siegel, 2003, “Critical Thinking”, in Blake et al. 2003: 181–193. doi:10.1002/9780470996294.ch11
  • Ben-Porath, Sigal R., 2006. Citizenship Under Fire: Democratic Education in Times of Conflict , Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
  • Blake, Nigel, Paul Smeyers, Richard Smith, and Paul Standish (eds.), 2003, The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Education , Oxford: Blackwell. doi:10.1002/9780470996294
  • Brighouse, Harry, 2005, On Education , London: Routledge.
  • –––, 2009, “Moral and Political Aims of Education”, in Siegel 2009: 35–51.
  • Brighouse, Harry and Adam Swift, 2009, “Educational Equality versus Educational Adequacy: A Critique of Anderson and Satz”, Journal of Applied Philosophy , 26(2): 117–128. doi:10.1111/j.1468-5930.2009.00438.x
  • Bull, Barry L., 2008, Social Justice in Education: An Introduction , New York: Palgrave MacMillan.
  • Burbules, Nicholas C., 1994, “Marxism and Educational Thought”, in The International Encyclopedia of Education , (Volume 6), Torsten Husén and T. Neville Postlethwaite (eds.), Oxford: Pergamon, second edition, pp. 3617–22.
  • Burnyeat, Myles F., 1980, “Aristotle on Learning to be Good”, in Amélie Oksenberg Rorty (ed.), Essays on Aristotle’s Ethics , Berkeley CA: University of California Press, pp. 69–92.
  • Callan, Eamonn, 1997, Creating Citizens: Political Education and Liberal Democracy , Oxford: Clarendon Press. doi:10.1093/0198292589.001.0001
  • –––, 2006, “Love, Idolatry, and Patriotism”, Social Theory and Practice , 32(4): 525–546. doi:10.5840/soctheorpract200632430
  • Carr, David, 2003, Making Sense of Education: An Introduction to the Philosophy and Theory of Education and Teaching , London: RoutledgeFalmer.
  • Carter, J. Adam and Ben Kotzee, 2015, “Epistemology of Education”, Oxford Bibliographies Online , last modified: 26 October 2015.
  • Carter, J.Adam and Duncan Pritchard, 2017, “Epistemic Situationism, Epistemic Dependence, and the Epistemology of Education”, in Abrol Fairweather and Mark Alfano (eds.), Epistemic Situationism , Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 168–191. doi:10.1093/oso/9780199688234.003.0010
  • Cartwright, Nancy D., 2013, Evidence: For Policy and Wheresoever Rigor Is a Must , London: London School of Economics and Political Science.
  • Cartwright, Nancy D. and Jeremy Hardie, 2012, Evidence-based Policy: A Practical Guide to Doing It Better , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Chambliss, J.J. (ed.), 1996a, Philosophy of Education: An Encyclopedia , New York: Garland.
  • Chambliss, J.J., 1996b, “History of Philosophy of Education”, in Chambliss 1996a, pp. 461–472.
  • Clayton, Matthew, 2006, Justice and Legitimacy in Upbringing , Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/0199268940.001.0001
  • Cleverley, John and D.C. Phillips, 1986, Visions of Childhood: Influential Models from Locke to Spock , New York: Teachers College Press.
  • Curren, Randall R., 1998, “Education, Philosophy of”, in E.J. Craig (ed.), Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy , vol. 3, pp. 231–240.
  • –––, 2000, Aristotle on the Necessity of Public Education , Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
  • –––, (ed.), 2003, A Companion to the Philosophy of Education , Oxford: Blackwell. doi:10.1002/9780470996454
  • –––, (ed.), 2007, Philosophy of Education: An Anthology , Oxford: Blackwell.
  • –––, 2013, “A Neo-Aristotelian Account of Education, Justice and the Human Good”, Theory and Research in Education , 11(3): 231–249. doi:10.1177/1477878513498182
  • –––, 2018, “Education, History of Philosophy of”, revised second version, in Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Online . doi:10.4324/9780415249126-N014-2
  • Curren, Randall, Emily Robertson, and Paul Hager, 2003, “The Analytical Movement”, in Curren 2003: 176–191. doi:10.1002/9780470996454.ch13
  • Curren, Randall and Charles Dorn, 2018, Patriotic Education in a Global Age , Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  • Dworkin, Ronald, 1977, Taking Rights Seriously , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Elgin, Catherine Z., 1999a, “Epistemology’s Ends, Pedagogy’s Prospects”, Facta Philosophica , 1: 39–54
  • –––, 1999b, “Education and the Advancement of Understanding”, in David M. Steiner (ed.), Proceedings of the 20 th World Congress of Philosophy , vol. 3, Philosophy Documentation Center, pp. 131–140.
  • Galston, William A., 1991, Liberal Purposes: Goods, Virtues, and Diversity in the Liberal State , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9781139172462
  • Gellner, Ernest, 1959, Words and Things: A Critical Account of Linguistic Philosophy and a Study in Ideology , London: Gollancz.
  • Gilligan, Carol, 1982, In a Different Voice: Psychological Theory and Women’s Development , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Goldberg, Sanford, 2013, “Epistemic Dependence in Testimonial Belief, in the Classroom and Beyond”, Journal of Philosophy of Education , 47(2): 168–186. doi:10.1111/1467-9752.12019
  • Goldman, Alvin I., 1999, Knowledge in a Social World , Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/0198238207.001.0001
  • Greene, Maxine, 1988, The Dialectic of Freedom , New York: Teachers College Press.
  • Gutmann, Amy and Dennis F. Thompson, 1996, Democracy and Disagreement , Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.
  • Hand, Michael, 2006, “Against Autonomy as an Educational Aim”, Oxford Review of Education , 32(4): 535–550. doi:10.1080/03054980600884250
  • Hardie, Charles Dunn, 1941 [1962], Truth and Fallacy in Educational Theory , New York: Teachers College Bureau of Publications.
  • Hirst, Paul, 1965, “Liberal Education and the Nature of Knowledge”, in Philosophical Analysis and Education , Reginald D. Archambault, (ed.), London: Routledge, pp. 113–138.
  • Hirst, Paul and R.S. Peters, 1970, The Logic of Education , London: Routledge.
  • Hollis, Martin, 1982, “Education as A Positional Good”, Journal of Philosophy of Education , 16(2): 235–244. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9752.1982.tb00615.x
  • Howe, Kenneth R., 2003, Closing Methodological Divides: Toward Democratic Educational Research , Dordrecht: Kluwer. doi:10.1007/0-306-47984-2
  • Jacobs, Lesley A., 2010, “Equality, Adequacy, And Stakes Fairness: Retrieving the Equal Opportunities in Education Approach”, Theory and Research in Education , 8(3): 249–268. doi:10.1177/1477878510381627
  • Kotzee, Ben (ed.), 2013, Education and the Growth of Knowledge: Perspectives from Social and Virtue Epistemology , Oxford: Wiley. doi:10.1002/9781118721254
  • Kristjánsson, Kristján, 2015, Aristotelian Character Education , London: Routledge.
  • –––, 2017, “Emotions Targeting Moral Exemplarity: Making Sense of the Logical Geography of Admiration, Emulation and Elevation”, Theory and Research in Education , 15(1): 20–37. doi:10.1177/1477878517695679
  • Kvernbekk, Tone, 2015, Evidence-based Practice in Education: Functions of Evidence and Causal Presuppositions , London: Routledge.
  • Lagemann, Ellen Condliffe, 2000, An Elusive Science: The Troubling History of Educational Research , Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  • Locke, J., 1693, Some Thoughts Concerning Education , London: Black Swan in Paternoster Row.
  • Lucas, Christopher J. (ed.), 1969, What is Philosophy of Education? , London: Macmillan.
  • Lyotard, J-F., 1984, The Postmodern Condition: A Report on Knowledge , Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
  • MacIntyre, Alasdair, 1984, After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory , second edition, Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.
  • Martin, Jane Roland, 1985, Reclaiming a Conversation: The Ideal of the Educated Woman , New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
  • Mehta, Ved, 1963, Fly and the Fly-Bottle: Encounters with British Intellectuals , London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson.
  • Miller, Richard W., 2007, “Unlearning American Patriotism”, Theory and Research in Education , 5(1): 7–21. doi:10.1177/1477878507073602
  • National Research Council (NRC), 2002, Scientific Research in Education , Washington, DC: National Academies Press. [ NRC 2002 available online ]
  • Noddings, Nel, 1984, Caring: A Feminine Approach to Ethics and Moral Education , Berkeley: University of California Press.
  • –––, 1992, The Challenge to Care in Schools: An Alternative Approach to Education , New York: Teachers College Press.
  • –––, 2015, Philosophy of Education , fourth edition, Boulder, CO: Westview.
  • O’Connor, D.J., 1957, An Introduction to Philosophy of Education , London: Routledge.
  • Park, J., (ed.), 1965, Bertrand Russell on Education , London: Allen and Unwin.
  • Peters, R.S., (ed.), 1973, The Philosophy of Education , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 1981, Moral Development and Moral Education , London: G. Allen & Unwin.
  • Phillips, D.C., 1985, “Philosophy of Education”, in International Encyclopedia of Education , Torsten Husén and T. Neville Postlethwaite, (eds.), pp. 3859–3877.
  • –––, 1987, Philosophy, Science, and Social Inquiry: Contemporary Methodological Controversies in Social Science and Related Applied Fields of Research , Oxford: Pergamon.
  • –––, 2009, “Empirical Educational Research: Charting Philosophical Disagreements in an Undisciplined Field”, in Siegel 2009: 381–406.
  • –––, 2010, “What Is Philosophy of Education?”, in Bailey et al. 2010: 3–19. doi:10.4135/9781446200872.n1
  • –––, (ed.), 2014, Encyclopedia of Educational Theory and Philosophy , Los Angeles: Sage.
  • Pritchard, Duncan, 2013, “Epistemic Virtue and the Epistemology of Education”, Journal of Philosophy of Education , 47(2): 236–247. doi:10.1111/1467-9752.12022
  • –––, 2016, “Intellectual Virtue, Extended Cognition, and the Epistemology of Education”, in Baehr 2016: 113–127.
  • Rawls, John, 1971, A Theory of Justice , Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.
  • –––, 1993, Political Liberalism , New York: Columbia University Press.
  • Robertson, Emily, 2009, “The Epistemic Aims of Education”, in Siegel 2009: 11–34.
  • Rorty, Amélie Oksenberg (ed.), 1998, Philosophers on Education: New Historical Perspectives , New York: Routledge.
  • Satz, Debra, 2007, “Equality, Adequacy, and Education for Citizenship”, Ethics , 117(4): 623–648. doi:10.1086/518805
  • Scheffler, Israel, 1960, The Language of Education , Springfield, IL: Thomas.
  • –––, 1965, Conditions of Knowledge: An Introduction to Epistemology and Education , Chicago: Scott, Foresman.
  • –––, 1973 [1989], Reason and Teaching , Indianapolis, IN: Hackett.
  • Schouten, Gina, 2012, “Fair Educational Opportunity and the Distribution of Natural Ability: Toward a Prioritarian Principle of Educational Justice”, Journal of Philosophy of Education , 46(3): 472–491. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9752.2012.00863.x
  • Scriven, Michael, 1991a, “Beyond Formative and Summative Evaluation”, in Milbrey McLaughlin and D.C. Phillips (eds.), Evaluation and Education: At Quarter Century , Chicago: University of Chicago Press/NSSE, pp. 19–64.
  • –––, 1991b, Evaluation Thesaurus , Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
  • Siegel, Harvey, 1988, Educating Reason: Rationality, Critical Thinking, and Education , New York: Routledge.
  • –––, 1997, Rationality Redeemed?: Further Dialogues on an Educational Ideal , New York: Routledge.
  • –––, 2004, “Epistemology and Education: An Incomplete Guide to the Social-Epistemological Issues”, Episteme , 1(2): 129–137. doi:10.3366/epi.2004.1.2.129
  • –––, 2005, “Truth, Thinking, Testimony and Trust: Alvin Goldman on Epistemology and Education”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research , 71(2): 345–366. doi:10.1111/j.1933-1592.2005.tb00452.x
  • –––, 2007, “Philosophy of Education”, in Britannica Online Encyclopedia , last modified 2 February 2018. URL = <https://academic.eb.com/levels/collegiate/article/philosophy-of-education/108550>
  • –––, (ed.), 2009, The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Education , New York: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780195312881.001.0001
  • –––, 2016, “Israel Scheffler”, In J. A Palmer (ed.), Routledge Encyclopaedia of Educational Thinkers , London: Routledge, pp. 428–432.
  • –––, 2017, Education’s Epistemology: Rationality, Diversity, and Critical Thinking , New York: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 2018, “The Epistemology of Education”, Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Online , doi:10.4324/0123456789-P074-1.
  • Skinner, B.F., 1948 [1962], Walden Two , New York: Macmillan.
  • –––, 1972, Beyond Freedom and Dignity , London: Jonathan Cape.
  • Smeyers, Paulus, 1994, “Philosophy of Education: Western European Perspectives”, in The International Encyclopedia of Education , (Volume 8), Torsten Husén and T. Neville Postlethwaite, (eds.), Oxford: Pergamon, second Edition, pp. 4456–61.
  • Smith, B. Othanel and Robert H. Ennis (eds.), 1961, Language and Concepts in Education , Chicago: Rand McNally.
  • Snook, I.A., 1972, Indoctrination and Education , London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
  • Stone, Lynda (ed.), 1994, The Education Feminism Reader , New York: Routledge.
  • Strike, Kenneth A., 2010, Small Schools and Strong Communities: A Third Way of School Reform , New York: Teachers College Press.
  • Warnick, Bryan R., 2015, “Taming the Conflict over Educational Equality”, Journal of Applied Philosophy , 32(1): 50–66. doi:10.1111/japp.12066
  • Watson, Lani, 2016, “The Epistemology of Education”, Philosophy Compass , 11(3): 146–159. doi:10.1111/phc3.12316
  • Winch, Christopher and John Gingell, 1999, Key Concepts in the Philosophy of Education , London: Routledge.
How to cite this entry . Preview the PDF version of this entry at the Friends of the SEP Society . Look up topics and thinkers related to this entry at the Internet Philosophy Ontology Project (InPhO). Enhanced bibliography for this entry at PhilPapers , with links to its database.
  • PES (Philosophy of Education Society, North America)
  • PESA (Philosophy of Education Society of Australasia)
  • PESGB (Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain)
  • INPE (International Network of Philosophers of Education)

autonomy: personal | Dewey, John | feminist philosophy, interventions: ethics | feminist philosophy, interventions: liberal feminism | feminist philosophy, interventions: political philosophy | feminist philosophy, topics: perspectives on autonomy | feminist philosophy, topics: perspectives on disability | Foucault, Michel | Gadamer, Hans-Georg | liberalism | Locke, John | Lyotard, Jean François | -->ordinary language --> | Plato | postmodernism | Rawls, John | rights: of children | Rousseau, Jean Jacques

Acknowledgments

The authors and editors would like to thank Randall Curren for sending a number of constructive suggestions for the Summer 2018 update of this entry.

Copyright © 2018 by Harvey Siegel D.C. Phillips Eamonn Callan

  • Accessibility

Support SEP

Mirror sites.

View this site from another server:

  • Info about mirror sites

The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy is copyright © 2023 by The Metaphysics Research Lab , Department of Philosophy, Stanford University

Library of Congress Catalog Data: ISSN 1095-5054

Theories of teaching and learning Essay

Introduction, bio-ecological theory, intellectual development theory, psychosocial theory, social cultural theory.

Theories of teaching and learning are mainly the steps taken in the process of educating children. Below are examples of theories of teaching and learning:

This theory is mainly characterized by change in a child’s development which is influenced by the relationship in the external factors.

Bronfenbrenners developed this theory associating a child’s development to its environment; the name of the theory was later changed to bio-ecological theory because he believed a child’s own biology is the primary environment that influences the child’s development.

Interaction between a child and its environment is different depending on how close they are and this can be discussed under the following subtopics; microsystem – the is the closest layer to the child mainly the parents who influence the development of the child (Berk & Winsler 1995).

Those close to the child also includes the family, church, school and neighbors, they can either bring the child closer or make the child move further away (Bronfenbrenner 1990).

Exosytem – this includes the larger social systems where the child is not involved directly but through those who are close to him but contributes to his development..

Macro-system and chrono-system-macro-system is the outermost developmental tool which comprises of beliefs, customs and law while chrono-system is mainly the time dimension of things as it relates to a child’s environment.

Intellectual theory is basically a theory of knowledge that states that people get knowledge and meaning of things from interactions between their experiences and ideas.

In the past intellectual theory was not valued they viewed knowledge as us use of common sense for example people in the traditional set up did not see the value of children playing however Jean Piaget did not agree with the traditional view as he saw play as an important and necessary part of the student’s cognitive development.

He argued that knowledge is found from experience through the process of accommodation and assimilation (Woodfolk & Margetts 2007). Constructivist theories are influential and students are expected to learn main ideas on their own through discovery learning.

Teachers at this stage need to be innovative and creative; they should arrange the classrooms in a manner that will make students able to think beyond the literacy focus for example making use of the available technology like introduction of the interactive whiteboard with pictures and numbers (Leiteberg 1976).

“The psychosocial development theory by Erickson explains eight stages under which a child develops from childhood through to be an adult.

The first stage in the theory is the infant stage from birth to one year. This is the stage where the child depends on the parents fully right from dressing, food, and comfort.

Parents are expected to expose the child to warmth, reliable, and dependable affection, hence making the child secure, also he is visited by friends and relatives in this stage. Childhood, 2 to 4 years – this is the stage where the child begins to explore their surroundings.

During this particular stage, parents are encouraged to be on the watch out especially in the activities their children are involved in as they tend to be curious of so many things some of which are dangerous. Kids also tend to develop their first interests like he wants to go out all the time and sometimes enjoy music playing on the radio.

Preschool, 4 to 6 years – during this stage, a child is noted to have the desire to do what the people around him/her are doing. A child who is at this stage is able to identify and note what is going on around them.

It is at this stage that as an adult one would make up stories that would explain to a child what is really going on around us. According to him the struggle experienced during this stage is resolved by identifying the social role of an individual (Honig Fetterman 1992).

School going Age: 6 to 12 Years – the stage marks the period where a child can learn create and achieve a number of things through acquired skills and knowledge.

During this stage a child is able to relate with his/her peers. Its important to note that when one a child experiences any social discrimination during this stage it is most likely to destroy the child’s self esteem and also creates room for other social problems to arise.

For this theory to be realized in the classroom, it is important for the teachers to have classroom principles from cognitive psychology which involves meaningful learning, organization, visual materials and good explanations given (Moll 1994).

Adolescence: 12 to 18 Years – this is the stage associated with identity and role of the kids. Young adulthood: 18 to 35 – categorized with solidarity and intimacy.

This is the stage where they believe to be grown ups and they can survive on there on they even get intimacy at this stage.

Middle Adulthood: 35 to 55 or 65 and Late Adulthood: 55 or 65 to Death – this is the final stages in this theory, they concentrate more on work adults may reach this stage and start being misery at their experiences and perceived failures.

Hewson, Posner, Strike & Gertzog, are the people who came up with the social cultural theory. This theory was developed by a team of competent scientific researchers and philosopher in the 1980s at the Cornell University.

It states that revolution has been taking place on a consistent pattern first a dominant scientific paradigm which was a way of seeing, thinking, valuing and doing things evolving from the interpersonal to the intrapersonal. (Wooldfolk 2004).

According to the theory, social interaction to the child results into step by step growth of the child as well as behavioral change. Vygotsky believes that development is of a child depends on the way the child interacts with the people around them and the things around them.

The theory is categorized into three stages: The first stage is learning through imitation, the second stage is by learning through instructions that requires the child to remember instructions from the instructor and use these instructions to self-control.

The last stage is through collaborative learning, these involves a group of people who understand each other and work together it can be categorized with peer pressure (Ormrod 2003). A supportive classroom is important where the child feels free and can talk freely to the teachers and other students promote his development.

Teachers should create an environment where there are lots of tools that can be used to manipulate the students’ way of thinking and develop an understanding, for example the teacher can use questions as a way of confirming if they recognized the concept and correct where they are wrong and also help refine their thinking, students learn new information more easily when they can relate it to something they already know (Kane 1996).

Those who are learning are normally resistant to change because they believe in what they know however cognitive conflicts have been used to develop strategies in teaching for conceptual change (Snowman 2009).

In conclusion the theories of teaching and learning are important because they help the teachers to meet the instructional needs of all the students and help them grow up from dependent to independent adult people.

The teachers in this case have a duty to set up a classroom that is attractive and comfortable so as to enable the children to be free and can discuss issues with there teachers without fear.

Finally the teachers must keep in mind that how they treat and educate the students will determine there future therefore they should set a good background in order to create a better future for them.

Addison, J. T. (1992). Urie Bronfenbrenner. Human Ecology , 20(2), 16-20.

Berk, E. & Winsler, A. (1995). Scaffolding Children’s Learning: Vygotsky and Early Childhood Education .

Berk, L. E. (2000). Child Development (5th ed.). Boston: Allyn and Bacon. Washington, DC: National Association for the Education of Young Children.

Bronfenbrenner, U. (1990). Discovering what families do. In Rebuilding the Nest: A New Commitment to the American Family. Family Service America . Web.

Honig, W., Fetterman J. G. (1992). Cognitive Aspects of Stimulus Control . Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum.

Kane, R., (1996). The Significance of Free Will . Oxford: Oxford.

Killeen, P. (1987). “Emergent Behaviorism”, in S. Modgil and C. Modgil (eds.), B. F. Skinner: Consensus and Controversy , New York: Falmer.

Leiteberg, H. (1976). Handbook of Behavior Modification and Behavior Therapy , Englewoood Cliffs, N. J.: Prentice-Hall.

McInerney, D.M. & McInerney, V. (2006). Educational Psychology: Constructing Learning (4 th edition). Frenchs Forest: Pearson Education.

Moll, C. (1994). Vygotsky and Education: Instructional implications and applications of sociohistorical psychology . New York: Cambridge University Press.

Ormrod, J. E. (2003). Educational Psychology: Developing Learners (4 th Ed.) . Merrill Prentice Hall: Upper Saddle River.

Snowman, J. (Ed). (2009). Psychology – Applied to teaching – 1st Australian Edition. Milton, Qld: John Wiley & Sons.

Woodfolk, A. & Margetts, K. (2007). Educational Psychology. Frenchs Forest: Pearson Education.

Wooldfolk, A. (2004). Educational Psychology – International Edition. Boston: Pearson and Allyn & Bacon.

  • Chicago (A-D)
  • Chicago (N-B)

IvyPanda. (2024, February 1). Theories of teaching and learning. https://ivypanda.com/essays/theories-of-teaching-and-learning/

"Theories of teaching and learning." IvyPanda , 1 Feb. 2024, ivypanda.com/essays/theories-of-teaching-and-learning/.

IvyPanda . (2024) 'Theories of teaching and learning'. 1 February.

IvyPanda . 2024. "Theories of teaching and learning." February 1, 2024. https://ivypanda.com/essays/theories-of-teaching-and-learning/.

1. IvyPanda . "Theories of teaching and learning." February 1, 2024. https://ivypanda.com/essays/theories-of-teaching-and-learning/.

Bibliography

IvyPanda . "Theories of teaching and learning." February 1, 2024. https://ivypanda.com/essays/theories-of-teaching-and-learning/.

  • The Bioecological Model of Human Development
  • Bronfenbrenner's Bioecological System Theory
  • The Nature and Nurture of Talent: A Bioecological Perspective
  • Professionalism in the Early Childhood Environment
  • Instagram Influence on Child Development
  • Paradigm: Knowledge Development and Practice Theories Selection
  • Global Issue: WWF on Bio-Refineries
  • Handling of Bio-Terrorist Threats
  • Agricultural, Economics and Environmental Considerations of Bio-Fuels
  • Are Government Bio Fuel Incentives Raising Food Prices?
  • Comparing First and Second Language Acquisition Theories
  • Is Class Size Crucial to School Improvement
  • Advantages and Disadvantages of E-Learning
  • Cooperation Versus Competition Approach in Learning and Evaluation of Student Achievement
  • New Experience in Learning by Mandy Navasero

Writing Universe - logo

  • Environment
  • Information Science
  • Social Issues
  • Argumentative
  • Cause and Effect
  • Classification
  • Compare and Contrast
  • Descriptive
  • Exemplification
  • Informative
  • Controversial
  • Exploratory
  • What Is an Essay
  • Length of an Essay
  • Generate Ideas
  • Types of Essays
  • Structuring an Essay
  • Outline For Essay
  • Essay Introduction
  • Thesis Statement
  • Body of an Essay
  • Writing a Conclusion
  • Essay Writing Tips
  • Drafting an Essay
  • Revision Process
  • Fix a Broken Essay
  • Format of an Essay
  • Essay Examples
  • Essay Checklist
  • Essay Writing Service
  • Pay for Research Paper
  • Write My Research Paper
  • Write My Essay
  • Custom Essay Writing Service
  • Admission Essay Writing Service
  • Pay for Essay
  • Academic Ghostwriting
  • Write My Book Report
  • Case Study Writing Service
  • Dissertation Writing Service
  • Coursework Writing Service
  • Lab Report Writing Service
  • Do My Assignment
  • Buy College Papers
  • Capstone Project Writing Service
  • Buy Research Paper
  • Custom Essays for Sale

Can’t find a perfect paper?

  • Free Essay Samples

Theories of Teaching

Updated 24 November 2023

Subject Learning

Downloads 40

Category Education

Topic Education System ,  Teacher

Teaching has always been packed with new philosophies about learning and teaching. Instructors are regularly blitzed with thoughts for reform. They are requested to use new syllabuses, new teaching tactics, and new valuations. They are focused to prepare scholars for the current state even test or to document and evaluate scholars’ effort through groups and presentation assessments.

Pedagogy is the method and practice of training especially as an educational subject or academic theory. It is also known as formal teaching, where the trainer directs all the learning processes. Informal teaching is known as andragogy, where the student is the focus, for instance, through team work and dialogs. Pedagogy regularly focuses on lessons of a similar topic at the same stage to all students and does not constantly allow the distinct knowledge to be taken into account. In the scenario given we tried to take into account the theory involved. Eliza brings a large cardboard box containing an entire cat skeleton that she discovered under the new home that their household had moved into and when the teacher asks her to open it, there are mixed reactions among the students most especially Ahmed who is puzzled and begins to cry when he realizes it was once a breathing animal like his pet. Therefore, the theory involved would be intellectual theory whereby, info understanding is centered on the thinking process. Variations in behavior are not seen only as a pointer to what the student is thinking. Learning takes place through internal processing of info. The intellectual style to learning theory puts into consideration what a student is thinking and concentrates on mental procedures rather than observable behavior (Peters, 1999). Variations in performance are seen and used as signs as to what a student is thinking. Ahmed’s reaction is based on emotions and mental frustrations when he thinks that the same could happen to his pet Tiggy.

Some of the other theories we discussed in groups were behaviorism and humanism theories. Behaviorism adopts that a student is fundamentally reflexive and will be shaped through constructive or undesirable reinforcement. Learning is therefore well-defined as a change in behavior (Blaise, 2011). Giving instant response, whether constructive or undesirable, should enable the student to act in a specific way. Behavior changes according to its direct consequences. The probability that the antecedent behavior will happen again is increased by both positive and negative reinforcements. Primary rein forcers please elementary human requirements while secondary rein forcers get their importance for being linked with primary rein forcers. An example of a positive reinforcement scenario, Mrs. Jacob’s third grade class is behaving below par. She resolves to cultivate a behavior controlling structure for her learners in the hope that it will inspire them to behave well. At the end of each lesson, if the students have adhered to the instructions at a tolerable level, Mrs. Jacob puts a score mark on the board. Every day, if there are more than eight score marks, Mrs. Jacob draws a star on the board. Once ten stars have been drawn, the class will get a biscuit party. She is optimistic that the motivation of a biscuit party will motivate them to follow the guidelines. On a negative scenario, Student-athletes are required to maintain a minimum grade of a B in every course in order to take part in their various sports. If a grade goes below a B, the student will not be allowed to participate until he or she improves the grade. The negative reinforcement of not being allowed to compete frequently motives a learner to rapidly do what is required to improve his or her grade. Positive shows the application of motivation while negative shows the withholding of motivation. Behaviorism is centered on the impression that behaviors are attained through conditioning which happens through interaction with the surroundings. There exist two categories of conditioning, one is classical conditioning where the neutral motivation is paired with a naturally occurring motivation. The second type of conditioning is operant conditioning which occurs through punishments and reinforcements. An association is usually made between a behavior and the consequences for the behavior (MacNaughton, 2009).

Humanism is a theory that considers learning as an individual act to achieve potential. Humanists believe that it is essential to learn a person as a whole, mainly as they grow and develop in life (Bronfenbrenner, 1994). The theory of facilitative learning was created based on a belief that people have a natural humanoid zeal to learn and that knowledge includes changing one’s own perception. This theory proposes that education will happen if the person delivering it acts as an initiator. The facilitator should create an atmosphere in which students feel comfortable and have the ability to discuss new concepts and study from their errors, as long as they are not exposed by external influences (Albon, 2011). For instance, Collins wants to be a basketball player when he grows up. He has the thought of school as a boring place and is annoyed when teachers try to make him study things that are not relevant to his life. To Collins, school seems dissimilar to his life and dreams, and so he is not able to study and grow. When scholars, like Collins, don't achieve their potential, it's because to some degree something is hindering them. In humanism control, efficiency and uniformity of scholars and trainers is valued over innovation, creativity, individuality and freedom. Teaching the set of courses becomes more significant than teaching the student. The theory is also based on the fact that all humans a natural tendency to learn, grow and develop completely. The main aim of human education is to create educational experiences that align with these natural needs (Quintero, 2007).

During the case study we were able to identify and predict five factors that contributed to effective learning environments. Motivation, is one of the most important factors in any learning atmosphere. Scholars have to be exceedingly motivated to study. Motivation is the dynamic strength that makes scholars stay with it even when they are experiencing difficulties in understanding info being offered during teaching (tchrishill1, 2009). Any difficulty related to learning can be overawed if the learner's inspiration is in abundance. The teachers as well have to be greatly encouraged to teach and must have the zeal to communicate info during teaching in a way scholar can comprehend. If learners are having trouble understanding, the teacher has to be inspired adequately to spend the additional time it takes to guarantee that the learner ultimately understands offered trainings.

Secondly, aptitude determines how fast and easy the learning process will be. The ability of the instructor in giving demonstrations, giving relevant comparisons, preparing descriptive images, scheming realistic rehearsal drills, and in common, observing the scholars’ attentiveness level will add to determining how rapidly and simple scholars understand new material. Teaching with propensity make it simple for scholars to study (Edwards, 2009). Third, presentation or demonstration is also the core of teaching. The well enhanced the teacher organizes and conveys the presentation, the simpler it will be for scholars to study. Presentation can entail, the teacher's lectures, demonstrations, replications, projector slides and visuals.

Repetition on the other hand, strengthens a scholar's understanding of well-educated material. Even scholars with tremendously great ability will find it hard to study from demonstrations made only one time (Fleer, 2010). All teaching sessions should start with a recap of recent demonstrations. Reviews also aid the teacher to limit difficult the topic is presented throughout each lesson. Being assured that definite material will be revised, the teacher can evade getting into complex topics through the first time the info is delivered. Lastly, practice with bolstering acts as the measure to evaluate the accomplishment of teaching. Well-made practice trainings should be accurate, making the learner to do things in a similar way they must when the exercise is finalized. Bolstering must be as an outcome of the scholars' rehearsal (Lindon, 2012). If the learner demonstrates a solid understanding of the offered information, corroboration should praise the success. On the other hand, if the exercise uncovers a scholar's lack of understanding, bolstering should come in the form of recurrent demonstrations and more training to ensure that the scholar ultimately understands the course.

Theoretical foundations categorize learning as behavioristic or intellectual. Behavioristic studying was the earliest pattern identified through case studies conducted. Psychologists defined knowledge as a change in behavior and used incentive response actions as case in point. Evolving from learning philosophies are descriptions of preferred methods or approaches to education. Classified as intellectual and learning methods, these approaches to learning are the ways that individuals gain knowledge, which is more apprehensive with method or procedure than content.

Albon, D. (2011). Postmodern and poststructuralist perspectives on early childhood                  education. In L. Miller " L. Pound (Eds.), Theories and approaches to learning in the   early years (pp. 38-52). London: Sage Publications.

Blaise, M. (2011). Teachers theory making. In G. Latham, M. Blaise, S. Dole, J. Faulkner " K.             Malone (Eds.), Learning to teach: New times, new practices (Vol. 2, pp. 105-157). South           Melbourne: Oxford University Press.

Bronfenbrenner, U. (1994). Ecological models of human development. In International             encyclopedia of education (2nd ed., Vol. 3, pp. 1643-1647). Oxford: Elsevier.

Crain, W. (2000). Theories of development 4 edn. New Jersey: Prentice Hall. pp. 361-373.

Education Week. (2013, January 9). Building a positive school climate [video file]. Retrieved        from https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=YNs6aFIpoTY

Edwards, S. (2009). Early childhood education and care: A sociocultural approach. Castle Hill,      NSW: Pademelon Press.

Fleer, M. (2010). Early learning and development (pp. 75-98). Cambridge: Cambridge             University Press.

Lindon, J. (2012). Children as part of a social and cultural community: Understanding child    development 0-8 years (Vol. 3, pp. 215-242). London: Hodder Education.

MacNaughton, G. (2009). Exploring critical constructivist perspectives on children's learning. In      A. Anning, J. Cullen " M. Fleer (Eds.), Early childhood education: Society and     culture (Vol. 2,           pp. 54-63). London: Sage Publications Ltd.

Peters, M. (1999). Poststructuralism and education. In M. Peters, T. Besley, A. Gibbons, B.     Žarnić " P. Ghiraldelli (Eds.), The encyclopaedia of educational philosophy and theory.           Retrieved from            http://eepat.net/doku.php?id=poststructuralism_and_philosophy_of_education

Quintero, E. (2007). Critical pedagogy and young children's worlds. In P. McLaren " J.             Kincheloe (Eds.), Critical pedagogy: Where are we now? (pp. 201-207). New York:   Peter Lang.

tchrishill1. (2009, September 26). The humanistic teacher [video file]. Retrieved from             https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=vqg8pNtILII

TEDxTalks. (2011, 30 June). TEDxOverlake - Dr Sara Goering - Philosophy for kids: Sparking          a love of learning [video file]. Retrieved from             https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=7DLzXAjscXk

Deadline is approaching?

Wait no more. Let us write you an essay from scratch

Related Essays

Related topics.

Find Out the Cost of Your Paper

Type your email

By clicking “Submit”, you agree to our Terms of Use and Privacy policy. Sometimes you will receive account related emails.

IMAGES

  1. Theory of teaching

    theory of teaching essay

  2. EDU10004 Theories of Teaching and Learning, Assignment 2 Essay

    theory of teaching essay

  3. Teachers Philosophy Of Education Examples

    theory of teaching essay

  4. Influence of Teaching Theories on Classroom Environment and

    theory of teaching essay

  5. Theory of Teaching Essay.docx

    theory of teaching essay

  6. iteach5600 Theory of Teaching Essay.docx

    theory of teaching essay

VIDEO

  1. Music Theory Teaching Introduction

  2. TEACHING ESSAY

  3. Theories of Teaching [NURSING EDUCATION]

  4. 5 timing tips for teaching the ToK Essay

  5. When it’s a scientific theory, it’s not “just a theory”

  6. Teaching: Reasoning Learning Targets

COMMENTS

  1. Introduction to the Most Important Theories of Teaching

    Learn about six important theories of teaching that guide classroom practice and curriculum design. Explore the concepts of multiple intelligences, Bloom's Taxonomy, ZPD, schema, behaviorism, and spiral curriculum.

  2. PDF Theories of Learning and Teaching What Do They Mean for Educators?

    Suzanne M. Wilson is a professor of education and director of the Center for the Scholarship of Teaching at Michigan State University. Her research interests include teacher learning, teacher knowledge, and connections between education reform and practice. Penelope L. Peterson is the dean of the School of Education and Social Policy and Eleanor R.

  3. Theories of Teaching and Learning Essay

    The effect individual theories have on an environment depends how they are incorporated within the classroom in addition to the influence they have had on the curriculum construction. This essay will briefly look at how motivation theory, cognitive and social cognitive theory along with constructivism have impacted on education and the classroom.

  4. PDF A Theory of Teaching

    This essay grapples with the framing questions offered by the book's editors: - What is a theory (of teaching)? ... With these characterizations in mind I discuss the idea of a theory of teaching - more generally, a theory of knowledge-based decision making in complex social contexts. The general question is as follows.

  5. A Theory of Teaching

    An answer to this question provides the goals for a theory of productive teaching (a theory of teaching aimed at desirable teaching outcomes, as suggested in Sect. 2). To cut to the chase, the Teaching for Robust Understanding (TRU) Framework (Schoenfeld, 2013, 2014; Teaching for Robust Understanding Project, 2018) provides the answer to the key question above.

  6. Critical Theories of Education: An Introduction

    This chapter gives an overall introduction to critical theories essential to education, as we lay out the histories, reasoning, needs, and overall structure of the Palgrave Handbook on Critical Theories of Education.We discuss the five groundings that are the conceptual and theoretical thematic constructions of the book as follows: praxis-oriented, fluidity, radical, utopic with countless ...

  7. John Dewey and Teacher Education

    Dewey's important essay, "The Relation of Theory to Practice in Education," is one of his few that specifically addresses the problems of preparing teachers to do the work of teaching. Dewey ( 1904a , p. 247) "assumes without argument" that both theory and practice are necessary components of teacher preparation; the question in his ...

  8. Philosophy of Education

    Philosophy of education is the branch of applied or practical philosophy concerned with the nature and aims of education and the philosophical problems arising from educational theory and practice. Because that practice is ubiquitous in and across human societies, its social and individual manifestations so varied, and its influence so profound ...

  9. Theories of Teaching and Learning

    This chapter contains sections titled: Classic Theories of Teaching and Learning John Dewey's Theory of Learning and Teaching Contemporary Constructivist Theories of Teaching and Learning The...

  10. Theories of Teaching and Learning

    This chapter contains sections titled: Classic Theories of Teaching and Learning John Dewey's Theory of Learning and Teaching Contemporary Constructivist Theories of Teaching and Learning The...

  11. Theories of teaching and learning

    This essay provides an overview of four theories of teaching and learning: bio-ecological, intellectual, psychosocial and social cultural. It explains the main concepts, stages and implications of each theory for education and development.

  12. (PDF) A Theory of Teaching

    The Merriam-W ebster dictionary ( 2020) de nes "teach" as follows: "to cause to know something… to guide the studies of… to impart the knowledge. of (e.g., teach algebra) to instruct by ...

  13. Theories of Teaching and Learning

    This essay discusses various educational theories, practices, and social and cultural factors that affect college students' learning and engagement. It also provides examples of how to apply these theories in tutoring sessions and curriculum design.

  14. PDF Theories of Teaching

    This theory conceives that teaching process helps to recollect or unfold that knowledge with questioning techniques. The teacher brings his knowledge at conscious level of this child. The focus of this theory is on self realization. The Socratic's method is an essential for this theory.

  15. iteach5600 Theory of Teaching Essay.docx

    5600 Theory of Teaching Essay From my prior knowledge of course 5200, I have learned about Learning Theories and Educational Philosophies. When reflecting on my teaching styles and beliefs over my years in education; I have developed a constructivist, progressivist and existentialist mindset for education. I believe that in order to be a great teacher you have to mix and match parts of many ...

  16. Theories of Teaching

    Teaching the set of courses becomes more significant than teaching the student. The theory is also based on the fact that all humans a natural tendency to learn, grow and develop completely. The main aim of human education is to create educational experiences that align with these natural needs (Quintero, 2007).

  17. Theory of Teaching Essay Assignment.docx

    Any Melendez 5600 Iteach 8/12/2023 Theory of Teaching Essay Assignment From my prior knowledge of course 5200, I have learned about Learning Theories and Educational Philosophies. When reflecting on my teaching styles and beliefs over my years in education, I have developed a constructivist, progressivist, and existentialist mindset for education. I believe that in order to be a great teacher ...

  18. Reflective Essay on Learning and Teaching

    ISSN: 2581-7922, Volume 2 Issue 5, September-October 2019. Kerwin A. Livingstone, PhD Page 57. Reflective Essay on Learning and Teaching. Kerwin Anthony Livingstone, PhD. Applied Linguist/Language ...

  19. Theory Of Teaching Essay (docx)

    Name Theory of Teaching Essay iTeach Texas 5600 When analyzing the different philosophies of education, I have decided that I am a mixture of multiple philosophies as I see the value in several of them and I might even take a little bit from all. I do think that basic core curriculum is important as the Essentialist believes, the importance of one's own gifts and talents is important as well ...

  20. (PDF) My Philosophy of Teaching and Learning

    The teaching philosophy usually is written as a short narrative essay that explains the teacher's personal reflection on the learning and teaching, the experiences obtained while conducting ...

  21. Theory of Teaching Essay.docx

    Theory of Teaching Essay In an ordinary learning environment, no two students are considered to be alike hence causing the variance experienced from person to person. This occurs because all our brains are built differently hence affecting how students can perform and gain knowledge and skills from a learning institution. As a teacher having the prior knowledge to handle such students is vital ...

  22. TEPC 5600 Theory of Teaching Essay Assignment 6

    Sociology document from No School, 2 pages, TEPC 5600 THEORY OF TEACHING ESSAY 4/4 Review all the material you have learned throughout the program, paying special attention to the theoretical orientations described in 5200. Spend some time reflecting on philosophies and theories of education and me

  23. ITeach 5600 theory of teaching (docx)

    iTeach TEPC 5600 Theory of Teaching Essay M.Mouton The ultimate goal in the career of a teacher is to successfully facilitate learning. There are many different avenues to do so; these avenues show varying success classroom-to-classroom and subject-to-subject. Knowing your students is the key to successfully teaching them. As an eighth grade mathematics teacher, I understand that all of my ...