Center for Justice Innovation logo

Fundamentals of Procedural Fairness

The Fundamentals of Procedural Justice

Professor Tom Tyler of Yale Law School and Chief Judge Jeffrey Kremers from Milwaukee introduce the concept of procedural justice and discuss how improved perceptions of fairness can yield significant benefits, including improved compliance with court orders, reduced recidivism, and improved public trust in justice.

Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.

To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to  upgrade your browser .

Enter the email address you signed up with and we'll email you a reset link.

  • We're Hiring!
  • Help Center

paper cover thumbnail

Procedural fairness as constitutional justice: an essay on Hans Kelsen’s theory of liberal constitutionalism

Profile image of Carl Lebeck

2008, Zeitschrift für öffentliches Recht

Related Papers

Niccolo Fantini

In this paper I tackle the vexata quaestio of constitutional courts and their justification. I argue for the integral necessity of constitutional court for liberal democratic systems. Departing from a liberal definition of democratic legitimacy, which identifies political obligation with democratic rule of law, I show that constitutional review of laws is inseparable from liberal democracy as a concept. To demonstrate this I survey the issue of Common Law and the political reality in the United Kingdom, which lacks a codified constitution. I conclude by taking up the question on whether the judiciary power should be separated from constitutional review as such, arguing for a separation that recognises the different but similar functions of the two powers.

essay on procedural fairness

The Cambridge Law Journal

Michael Foran

This paper explores the effect that conformity to the rule of law has on the ends which might legitimately be pursued within a legal system. The neat distinction between formal and substantive conceptions of the rule of law will be challenged: even apparently formal conceptions necessarily affect the content of law and necessarily entail the protection of certain fundamental rights. What remains of the formal/substantive dichotomy is, in fact, a distinction between conceptions of the rule of law which guarantee the substantive justice of each and every law and those which entail some commitment to basic requirements of justice while nevertheless leaving room for unjust laws. Ultimately, the only significant distinction between competing theories of the rule of law concerns the nature of the connection between legality and justice, not whether there is any such connection at all.

Law and Philosophy Library

Erik Oddvar Eriksen

William Pugliese

Christopher May

This chapter seeks to establish the role that the norm of the rule of law plays in the new constitutionalism, by establishing that the commonality of the rhetoric of the rule of law has seen it rise to a level of received wisdom or common sense in global politics. The chapter maps the problems with defining the norm before examining the role of agency in the widened use of and appeal to the rule of law. Without dismissing structural explanations, it concludes that the normativity of the rule of law is (re)produced through professional practice and technical legal assistance.

Patrick A Saigg

This work concerns is to emphasize the importance of relativistic thinking especially considering positive norms, not as a simple submission to the desire of others, but as a respect for our democratic system and the separation of powers. The aim of this work is not to make a judgment of value about the content of specific laws – in a non-axiological sens – but to try to understand how some rules, even socially considered as " unjust " , may be valid in a legal system. Addressing the theme of justice and the norm validity of law, which is fundamental to the understanding of the problem, this text finds its foundation in the guidelines drawn up by Hans Kelsen in his legal positivism grounded in skepticism and relativism.

Beijing Law Review

roberto scarciglia

Emanuela Ceva

This paper challenges the claim that proceduralism can say something relevant about the legitimacy, but not the justice of a polity. It is often argued that whilst legitimacy has to do with the mechanisms through which political coercive decisions are made (who exercises authority and how it is exercised), justice is more a substantial matter concerning the terms of social cooperation, against which the qualities of the decisions made by those who are entitled to make them are to be evaluated. Accordingly, the argument goes, an approach focusing on the qualities of procedures seems to be more appropriate for legitimacy than for justice. I contend that this characterization is inaccurate for it mixes three different issues which require, instead, separate theorizing: (i) who is entitled to make politically binding decisions? (ii) How should political decision making processes be structured? And (iii) how should political decisions be evaluated? I argue that considerations of legitimacy apply to level (i), whereas considerations of justice apply to levels (ii) and (iii). Although the appropriateness of a procedural approach to the justice-related question in (iii) is debatable, proceduralism seems well-equipped to provide a sound answer to the, equally justice-related, question in (ii). It does so by focusing on the way in which persons should be treated by the procedures through which they interact, once all issues of entitlement are set (i) and independently of the outcomes of the interaction (iii).

Ivan Cerovac

In discussions on democratic legitimacy, Christiano's position is often characterized as a monistic position, i.e. a strong and persuasive version of fair deliberative pro-ceduralism. Democracy is thus seen as a realization of public equality in collective decision making. The presented case for democracy is non-instrumental, and the quality of outcomes produced by a democratic decision-making process does not constitute or in any way influence the legitimacy – generating features of that decision-making process. I argue that the quality of political decisions produced by a democratic decision-making process should play an important (though not decisive) role in Christiano's argument. Consequently, I claim that his case for democracy should be (at least somewhat) instrumental. I consider four cases from Christiano's The Constitution of Equality that show how outcomes of democratic procedures are very important to Christiano. Furthermore, I argue that these outcomes are so important that, when deciding between two or more fair decision-making procedures, one that produces the best outcomes should be considered legitimate.

Evan Fox-Decent

Common law constitutionalism is the theory that legal principles such as fairness and equality reside within the common law, are constitutive of legality, and inform (or should inform) statutory interpretation on judicial review. This article looks to Rand J’s judgment in Roncarelli v. Duplessis to develop a democratic and relational conception of common law constitutionalism. By “democratic” I mean a version of the theory that governs judicial review but which is available to front-line decision-makers independently of the history and contemporary practice of review. By “relational” I mean a theory that presupposes the existence of a trust-like and legally significant relationship between public authorities and the persons subject to their power. Under the democratic and relational theory, the legality of administrative action is assessed in light of legal principles constitutive of the trust-like relationship and without reference to the separation of powers. These principles flow from the trust-like nature of the relationship and the implications of working out how public authorities can hold discretionary power over individuals without subjecting them to domination or instrumentalization.

RELATED PAPERS

VENDOR SEPATU

Brazilian Journal of Otorhinolaryngology (Impresso)

Pedro Luiz Mangabeira Albernaz

TED EĞİTİM VE BİLİM

Arzu Ozyurek

O Mundo da Saúde

Oscar Raposo

European Journal of Internal Medicine

Ramdhani Natsir

Dong K Dinh

Journal of Accounting and Taxation

aminu lawal

Journal of Medical Sciences

Iqbal Haider

William Rodi

Student Journal of International Law

lena farsia

Journal of International Social Research

Çiğdem Şerik

ACS Medicinal Chemistry Letters

Yulius Setiady

Letras Verdes, Revista Latinoamericana de Estudios Socioambientales

Juan Luna Pineda

Guy Laperrière

mustapha elagag

Frontiers in Nutrition

Theresa Waclawek

Journal of Clinical Oncology

Maria Grazia Grech

Scientific Reports

Dominique Taurisson-Mouret

Journal of Open Source Software

Christopher Wikle

International Journal of Christianity & Education

Darin Davis

European Journal of Ophthalmology

RISHIKESH THAKUR

Journal of Sport Pedagogy & Research

Luciana Venâncio

International Journal of Basic & Clinical Pharmacology

Lokesh Patil

RELATED TOPICS

  •   We're Hiring!
  •   Help Center
  • Find new research papers in:
  • Health Sciences
  • Earth Sciences
  • Cognitive Science
  • Mathematics
  • Computer Science
  • Academia ©2024

Site Logo

Bite-sized videos on access to justice issues

Procedural Fairness Online Course

Free online procedural fairness course now available

Procedural fairness (also referred to as procedural justice) is an evidence-based practice reliably associated with higher levels of compliance with and greater amounts of satisfaction with decisions by authority figures. Increasingly, national judicial organizations have recognized the importance of promoting procedural fairness. Recently, the Conference of Chief Justices and the Conference of State Court Administrators adopted a resolution encouraging state court leaders to promote the implementation of procedural fairness principles; a resolution in support of implementing clear communications and streamlined procedures in the courts; and a resolution encouraging leadership to promote equal justice.

We focus on helping judges and courts implement policies and practices that promote procedural fairness in courtrooms and courthouses. In addition, we look at policing, currently the focus of the majority of criminal justice research on procedural fairness, but we retain an emphasis on the courts.

We also seek to bridge the gap between academic research and actual practice. This site is a collaborative effort by judges, researchers, and university professors who share a belief that an emphasis on procedural fairness can make judges and court managers more effective decision makers, improve compliance with court orders, and increase public satisfaction with the court system. Yet we also share a desire to engage with one another—as well as a broader community—to test our ideas. So we provide a forum linking judges and court managers to the academic and research community engaged in the study of procedural fairness.

Procedural Fairness Blog

The founding participants are Judge Kevin Burke, District Judge in the Hennepin County (Minn.) District Court; Judge Steve Leben, Judge, Kansas Court of Appeals; the National Center for State Courts (with researcher David Rottman as its lead blogging participant); and Professor Tom Tyler, of Yale Law School.

Formative Law -->

Just another WordPress site

  • Self-Represent

Basic Elements of Procedural Fairness

Share this:

Procedural fairness affects all of us in our everyday lives. This lecture explains the concept of procedural fairness and its various manifestations in everyday scenarios.

This lecture is taught by Amer Mushtaq , LL.B., M. Engineering , B.Sc. (Hons.), who is the Principal and Founder of Formative LLP.   Through his YouTube channel, YouCounsel , Amer shares practical advice from his years of legal experience to help anyone access justice and achieve their goals.  Subscribe today to learn more.

Show Notes:

Lecture slides:.

Welcome to YouCounsel.

Procedural fairness impacts all of us —whether we’re in the court system or not, we are always dealing with procedural fairness in our everyday life.  In the court system you may have noticed that a number of my lectures are about procedure – whether it’s Rules of Civil Procedure (whether in small claims court procedure or family law procedure).  In a court system the procedures are often laid out/ defined in great detail because courts are concerned with the process by which the decision-making is done.  The court is trying to ensure that every party who is involved in a court process is entitled to a procedural fairness in that system.  But what happens in our lives outside of the court system? How does the procedural fairness impact all of us on a daily basis?  That is what this lecture is about.

We begin with our usual disclaimer that this lecture is not legal advice.  If you have any specific questions regarding your issues you should contact a lawyer or a paralegal or the Law Society of Ontario for a referral.

Who is affected by procedural fairness ?  As I stated, the answer is all of us —when we are dealing with the public or quasi public institutions—we are always dealing with issues of procedural fairness.  For example, when you apply for employment insurance, when you’re laid off from your employment or when you are ill or when you are on maternity leave or part of parental leave and whatnot you are dealing with procedural fairness – social benefits, welfare, disability matters all are dealt in procedural fairness.  When you are engaging health care, attending hospitals, universities, colleges, when you’re applying for a license (for example, a driver’s license or health card) – all of these instances are examples where procedural fairness is at play. Even in private institutions, for example, when an employer conducts a workplace investigation that investigation is bound by procedural fairness.  There are so many scenarios in our life where we are engaged with procedural fairness.

What is this procedural fairness? Procedural fairness is essentially fairness of the process / the procedure by which a decision is made .  Procedural fairness is not concerned about what is the end result / what is the end decision but the process by which that decision is made .  How do we understand this process?  

Let me give you an example. A complains that B has harassed him.  A comes to you as the employer.  That is the complaint.  You make the decision to penalize B without an opportunity for B being able to respond to the complaint—you believe that B has been harassing other employees all the time.  There have been many instances in the past that B was reprimanded or punished for his harassing behavior.  On the other hand you know A very well. He is a great person (likable person) who doesn’t lie, doesn’t cause trouble in the workplace.  On the basis of that information you just believe that there is no need for B to respond to these allegations – you must have done so and you go ahead and penalize B. That is essentially a violation of procedural fairness for B . Because you have denied B an opportunity to respond to that complaint and you’re taking a shot in the dark because there is 50 percent chance whether B harassed A or not.  By failing to give an opportunity for B to respond, you have violated his procedural fairness .  That’s an example of how procedural fairness works in the process.

What are some of the basic elements of procedural fairness ? There are essentially 2 principles and they are in Latin and the English is: 1. Number one is the right to be heard (this is one procedural fairness principle); and, the 2nd is the right to be judged impartially. Now these procedures manifest in many different ways.

Let’s go through the examples of how procedural fairness may work in different scenarios. 1st of all you should understand that the threshold that engages the duty of procedural fairness is quite low . What is that threshold? If an individual’s rights, privileges or interests are at issue then the procedural fairness is engaged and this is a very low threshold—because if you are affected by a decision then obviously your interests are at issue.  If you applied to a certain university and you believe that the admission process was unfair, of course your interests are engaged in the process.   Procedural fairness, number one, has a very low threshold to be engaged—I mean, I can’t imagine any scenario where you may not be entitled to procedural fairness but that’s what it is the threshold is quite low.

2nd what you want to remember is that procedural fairness is flexible and entirely dependent on context . The two principles that I’ve talked about the right to be heard and the right to be judged impartially, they are applied in the specific circumstances of the case.  That is why it is important to know that what may be a breach of procedural fairness in one context may be completely fair in another context.  Procedural fairness is context driven .  The courts or the administrative bodies are looking at the specific context of that case to decide what is procedurally fair in the circumstances of that case.

The 2 procedural fairness principles that we have talked about: the right to be heard and the right to be judged impartially have different manifestations in different circumstances .  I have listed some of the examples of these manifestations: number one is no undue delay .  If it is fair for you to get a decision in 30 days and you have not received a decision for 6 months, then, that may be an undue delay.  That may be a violation of your procedural right / procedural fairness.  You’re obviously entitled to a fair and impartial process .  We talked about it.  You are entitled to / have the right to know the case against you .  In the example that I have given, B is entitled to know what the complaint against him is—who made the complaint, so that he could respond to it.  Then the right to be heard . B is then entitled to do to be heard.  B is entitled to say his truth, to say his side of the story so that the decision maker can make a just and fair decision.

Legitimate expectation means that if you are a person who is affected by a certain decision and there are certain expectations given to you for that process, then those expectations are complied with.  For example, we know that in the Rules of Civil Procedure a party is entitled to file its defense within 20 days or 30 days in certain circumstances. That means that party is entitled not to be noted in default until that time runs out (20/30 days). If that party is noted in default earlier, then that’s a violation of the legitimate expectation of that party. Similarly, if you are entitled to a decision in 30 days and you don’t get that decision for 6 months or a year—that’s a violation of your procedural right for a legitimate expectation.

There is also a right called freedom to conduct one’s own case .  This is again specific to a scenario.  In this case, the Human Rights Tribunal had imposed on a party to provide “Will Say” statements for certain witnesses.  The party said we are entitled to present our case the way we want it.  You cannot force us to present our witnesses evidence.  They challenged that decision and the decision was overturned by the Divisional Court on the grounds that the party was entitled to present its case the way it sees fit—that it cannot be imposed on the party how it should present a case.

Right to reasons : in certain circumstances you may be entitled not only to know the decision but to know the reasons for that decision. An example of this right was in one case where a probationary police officer was terminated from his employment without giving any reasons. And the employer took the position that the Police Act allowed them to terminate the employee and therefore they didn’t need to provide any reasons.  The court said no, you are required to provide reasons to this particular probationary officer because it is procedurally unfair for him not to know the reasons and not to have an opportunity to respond to those reasons.  In certain circumstances this may be your procedural right – to know the reasons for the decision.

Similarly, in workplace investigations the person who is being penalized because of the outcome of that investigation may be entitled to know the reasons why the decision was made against that party. In circumstances where credibility is an issue we know that oral submissions are important .  In certain circumstances where a decision-making body denies one party to make oral submissions even though there were credibility issues that were at play, then it may be held that that was a denial of procedural fairness. 

In some circumstances you may be entitled to an adjournment of certain decision because you need a little bit more time to respond to certain things and it may be considered that if an adjournment is not given to you, in those circumstances, that may be a violation of procedural fairness.  In some circumstances we know that, for example, in a workplace investigation scenario, Occupational Health and Safety Act imposes an obligation on an employer to conduct an investigation for harassment.  In some other circumstances you may be entitled, based upon your complaint, to have an investigation and if the party or the employer in that circumstance does not conduct an investigation, that may be a violation of your right.

What is the take away: you have to always, always, always watch out for procedure . The devil may lie, the devil may work behind the procedure, greater injustice maybe happening because of lack of procedural fairness .  This is something that you need to always watch for. You need to always claim procedural fairness and you need to follow procedural fairness with respect to your rights and obligations.

Thank you for watching.

Related Videos:

  • Thinking like a Lawyer: Filtering Perspectives
  • Obtaining a Default Judgment in Ontario Superior…
  • Completing and Filing a Human Rights Application in…
  • Legal Options for Sexual Harassment/Discrimination Victims
  • Employment Insurance Benefits – A Brief Overview
  • Wrongfully dismissed in Ontario: Choosing the right court

This entry was posted on Monday, October 12th, 2020 at 3:40 pm and is filed under Uncategorized . You can follow any responses to this entry through the RSS 2.0 feed. Both comments and pings are currently closed.

Comments are closed.

Recent Videos:

  • Lecture 5: How to Claim Refunds in Canada for Summer Camps/Airline Tickets Due to COVID-19? November 13, 2020
  • Emergency Loan for Canadians Stranded Abroad During COVID-19 Pandemic November 13, 2020
  • New Changes (May 29) to Ontario’s Employment Laws: Employees Lose Rights During COVID-19 Emergency November 13, 2020
  • $1.2K+ per Month – Student Benefit (Canada Emergency Student Benefit) November 9, 2020
  • Lecture 4: How to Claim Refunds in Canada for Summer Camps/Airline Tickets Due to COVID-19? November 9, 2020

LOOKING TO HIRE A LAWYER OR SEEKING LEGAL ADVICE?

  • November 2020
  • October 2020
  • August 2020
  • January 2019
  • December 2017
  • November 2017
  • October 2017
  • September 2017

T: 416 542 1616 F: 416 342 1749 [email protected] [email protected]

334 Adelaide Street West, Suite 301 Toronto, Ontario M5V 0M1 350 Bay Street, Suite 1000 Toronto, Ontario M5H 2S6 --> www.formativelaw.ca

facebook

SERVING TORONTO, AJAX, BRAMPTON, BURLINGTON, ETOBICOKE, HAMILTON, KITCHENER-WATERLOO, LONDON, MARKHAM, MILTON, MISSISSAUGA, NORTH YORK, OAKVILLE, OSHAWA, PICKERING, RICHMOND HILL, SCARBOROUGH, ST. CATHARINES, VAUGHAN, AND WHITBY.

Resources -->

McGill Law Journal

Judicial Review and Procedural Fairness in Administrative Law: II

Table of contents.

McGILL LAW JOURNAL

REVUE DE DROIT DE McGILL

Judicial Review and Procedural Fairness in

Administrative Law: II

R. A. Macdonald*

The recent Canadian embrace of the doctrine of procedural fairness has led to a small flood of litigation and to a serious revaluation of the law of implied procedural review. In Part I of this essayt several themes were explored. An analysis of the historical foundations of due process supervision that, unlike jurisdictional control and review, for errors of law, it. does not rest on a constitutional theory about the role of the judiciary. Rather, it is founded on a particular theory of adjudication (adversarial adjudication), and it developed from the desire by the Court of King’s Bench to impose its model of dispute settlement on inferior jurisdictions exercising functions similar to those of the Court. Moreover, an examination of the intellectual context of procedural to common assumption, implied procedural review was not extended in the past, in any systematic fashion, to parliamentary delegates not exercising adjudicative functions. As a result, the justification for procedural supervision in non-judicial contexts must lie in some theory of procedural justice. Little specific guidance can be found in traditional literature on this topic, but some legal writing indicates that such a theory could be grounded on the democratic values of participation and consent. Neither of these values compels judicial procedural supervision, an adversarial paradigm for due process review, or the belief that procedural fairness can be objecti- fied in individual circumstances. A detailed review of the actual and potential applications of the new fairness doctrine revealed the possibilities for such a theory in a range of decision-making processes and in respect of informal, semi-formal and highly formalized statutory schemes. This review indicated that, even

that, contrary

*Associate Professor, Faculty of Law, McGill University. t (1980) 25 McGill LJ. 520.

McGILL LAW JOURNAL

in substantial when statutory procedural guidelines are promulgated detail, a role for implied procedural supervision could be justified. Ex- ploration of the potential impact of fairness thus seemed to reinforce the arguments its proponents advanced as to the need for wide-ranging procedural review. This Part will attempt a prescriptive analysis of the future of procedural review by examining its distinctive characteristics. From this examina- tion, the fundamental elements of an alternative concept of procedural fairness will be deduced. The essay will conclude with the formulation of a theory of procedural review of administrative action and an institu- tional model which exploits the possibilities of the emerging doctrine of fairness.

I. Towards a theory of implied procedural review

The law of procedural review in Canada has not developed markedly since the Supreme Court of Canada gave judgement in the Nicholson case,” and in many respects subsequent judgements have followed a pattern established in England. The vocabulary of procedural review may have changed but the concerns which pro- duced the quasi-judicial/administrative dichotomy remain; deci-

‘Re Nicholson & Haldimand-Norfolk Regional Board of Commissioners of Police [1979] 1 S.C.R. 311 per Laskin C.J.C., Ritchie, Spence, Dickson and Estey 13. concurring; Martland, Pigeon, Beetz and Pratte J3. dissenting. See Grey, The Duty to Act Fairly after Nicholson (1980) 25 McGill L.J. 598. This is not to say that the courts have ignored the doctrine: see, e.g., R. V. 98 (Ont. Div. Ct), aff’d 27 Chitty’s L.J. 174 Saikaly (1979) 27 Chitty’s L.. (Ont. C.A.); M.N.R. v. Coopers & Lybrand [1979] 1 S.C.R. 495; Re Webb & Ontario Housing Corp. (1978) 22 O.R. (2d) 257 (C.A.); Harvie v. Calgary (S.C. App. Div.); Inuit Regional Planning Commission (1978) 12 A.R. 505 Tapirisat v. Governor-in-Council [1979] 1 F.C. 710 (C.A.); Martineau & Butters v. Matsqui Institution Inmate Disciplinary Board (No. 2) (1979) 30 N.R. 119, 13 C.R. (3d) 1 (S.C.C.); Re Abel & Director, Penetanguishene Mental Health Centre (1979) 24 O.R. (2d) 279 (Div. Ct); Re Island Protection Society & The Queen (1979) 98 D.L.R. (3d) 504 (B.C.S.C.); Bruce & Meadley v. Reynett [1979] 2 F.C. 697 (T.D.); Re Rozander & Energy Resources Conservation Board (No. 2) (1979) 93 D.L.R. (3d) 284 (Alta S.C. App. Div.); Re Proctor (1979) 24 O.R. (2d) 715 (C.A.); Re S & M Laboratories Ltd & The Queen (1979) 24 O.R. (2d) 732 (CA.); Re Men’s Clothing Manufacturing Association & 26 O.R. (2d) 20 (Div. Ct); Re Gillingham & Metropolitan Arthurs (1979) Toronto Board of Commissioners of Police (1979) 26 O.R. (2d) 77 (Div. Ct); (C.A.); Re Peterson & Re Downing & Graydon (1978) 21 O.R. (2d) 292 Atkinson (1978) 23 O.R. (2d) 292 (C.A.); Re Brown & Waterloo Police Com- missioners (1979) 26 O.R. (2d) 746 (Div. Ct).

2 See Loughlin, Procedural Fairness: A Study of the Crisis in Administra- tive Law Theory (1978) 28 U.T.LJ. 215, 226-30 and cases such as Pearlberg v. Varty [1972] 1 W.L.R. 534 (H.L.); Bates v. Lord Hailsham [1972] 1 W.L.R. 1373 (Ch.); Selvarajan v. Race Relations Board [1976] 1 All E.R. 12 (C.A.). Cf. Denning, The Discipline of Law (1979), 88-96.

JUDICIAL REVIEW AND PROCEDURAL FAIRNESS

sions such as Coopers & Lybrand seem to retreat from the implica- tions of Nicholson by tying questions of procedural supervision to a classification of function approach 3 While recognizing the con- cept of fairness (and indeed asserting the possibility of procedural control over processes which previously would not have been characterized as judicial), courts have not sanctioned and followed a flexible approach to the supervision of due process, but have relied on a modified classification of function framework to struc- ture the process by which procedural formalities are implied.

Loughlin attempts to explain this conservatism by way of the traditional “rule of law” thesis which he feels underlies the com- mon law system. He argues that the theory of procedural fairness requires courts to engage in a purposive balancing of interests which runs counter to the assumptions of classical adjudication:

the court -would increasingly be tied to notions of instrumental rationality which, because that tends to destroy the idea of rule-governed behaviour, would then tend to destroy the basis for certainty, the distinctive nature of the adjudicative process, and thus destroy the symmetry of the traditional model. 4

In Loughlin’s view, judges appreciate that activism in applying a theory of fairness would vest them with power to determine how bureaucratic decisions should be taken.5 Since these determinations cannot be characterized as judicial decisions, in so far as they do not involve the invocation of a pre-existing normative structure, judges are loath to make them. Hence, by resisting what Loughlin describes as an informalist approach to implied review, the courts maintain the distinctiveness and moral force of decision-making institutions such as adjudication, and avoid administrative chaos by ovdr-judicialization of decisional processes. Loughlin concedes that an ad hoc approach to fairness in situations which closely resemble classical adjudication may improve certain aspects of the administrative process, provided that this does not imply the projection of adjudicative assumptions into non-adjudicative pro- cesses, and that the standards of procedural fairniess; although flexibly applied, are known and agreed.6

3 An excellent summary of the relationship between Nicholson and Coopers & Lybrand is contained in Mullan, Administrative Law (1980) 1 Supreme Ct L. Rev. 1, 2-20.

4 Supra, note 2, 237. For a more complete analysis of this theme see Arthurs, Rethinking Administrative Law: A Slightly Dicey Business (1979) 17 Osgoode Hall L.. 1.

5See Re Downing & Graydon, supra, note 1; Re Peterson & Atkinson, supra, note 1; Re Proctor, supra, note 1. But cf. Re Abel & Penetanguishene Mental Health Centre, supra, note 1; Re Gillingham, supra, note 1.

0 See supra, note 2, 240-1.

In view of this caution, advocates of an activist judicial approach to fairness are compelled to address the following question: is there any way to preserve the two main benefits which flow from adoption of the fairness doctrine, namely, the exposure of all administrative decision-making to review on procedural grounds, and the abandonment of a rigid bifurcation of statutory powers into judicial and administrative categories for the purposes of determining the content of procedural review, without compromis- ing the integrity of adjudication or the efficacy of administration? Investigation of this question may begin with an enumeration of the components of the fairness theory. Although the concept has been widely discussed in academic literature, few authors have identified the ends to which fairness should be invoked. Mullan, however, suggests:

[i]n some instances … it will mean nothing more than acting in good faith … . [W]hen the decision in question can be seen as much closer to the policy-oriented, traditionally “administrative” decision, the em- phasis is going to be on informality with written “hearings” the order of the day and no more than the gist of the relevant information avail- able to affected parties … . Beyond this … the courts will encounter the traditional kind of natural justice arguments and little will be changed here where the issues are matters such as representation by counsel, right to cross-examination, advance access to every scrap of relevant and marginally relevant paper, precision of issues, and the like.7 In other words, it appears that the concept of fairness is directed to what may broadly be identified as participation in decision- making.” As a result, the conditions under which any form of parti- cipation should be permitted, the precise nature of such parti- cipation in individual cases, and the constraints placed on decision- makers in order to guarantee the effectiveness of this participation are the fundamental elements of a theory of procedural fairness.

But fairness is also a theory of implied due process review; consequently it will be invoked subsidiarily in the interstices of a statutory procedural framework. Review for fairness, like review for natural justice, represents a distinctive kind of judicial super- vision, which does not share the same attributes as review on jurisdictional grounds. Therefore, proponents of this theory must first ask how fairness coheres with the general concept of implied procedural review in the Canadian legal system.

7Mullan, Fairness: The New Natural Justice? (1975) 25 U.T.L.J. 281, 314-5. 8The doctrine of fairness therefore should not be seen as involving any substantive element (cf. Grey, supra, note 1, 601-2), although it may wcll in- volve several elements not directly related to a “hearing” in the traditional sense of that term.

A. The distinctive character of implied procedural review

What are the salient characteristics of implied procedural re- view, and on what basis should this form of due process review be sustained in individual cases? In answering these questions one may emphasize three main themes. First, on no other ground of judicial review are the immediate interests of the disputing parties so connected to bureaucratic, non-legal concerns. Ultra vires review protects citizens from unauthorized exercises of governmental power, and review for errors of law controls the substantive legal framework of decision in particular instances; both usually have no long-term effect on the internal management of bureaucracies. By contrast, implied procedural review speaks neither to the statu- tory limits of a decision-maker’s power, nor to the pre-existing law he must apply, but, theoretically, only to the institutional pro- cedures by which decisions are made.’ Although these may not have a strictly logical connection with the substantive result reached in a given case, they reveal at least an ethical or aesthetic connec- tion.10 Consequently, the overwhelming majority of implied pro- cedural review cases, while phrased in the narrow legal language of a lis inter partes, manifest a larger institutional problem.

As has been noted, the revocation of parole without granting a hearing reflects not only a substantive injustice in an individual case but an abuse of decisional power within the National Parole Board;” ‘ the refusal to indicate what is defective in an applicant’s request for citizenship may reveal both the existence of prejudice against a particular person and a bureaucratic snag in the Ministry concerned;’2 and the failure to entertain the possibility of attitu- dinal bias in a Royal Commissioner probably has more to do with a theoretical misconception of the role of inquiries than an attempt to defeat the interests of the applicant. 13 In each example, statutory

9 0f course, review for procedural ultra vires is more akin to review for formal ultra vires. In both these cases, one is challenging administrative activity on the grounds that statutory provisions have not been followed.

10 See Macdonald, Judicial Review and Procedural Fairness in Administra- tive Law: I (1980) 25 McGiU LJ. 520, 536-42; Fuller, A Reply to Professors Cohen and Dworkin (1965) 10 Villanova L. Rev. 655, 665-6.

“See Howarth v. National Parole Board [1976] 1 S.C.R. 453, and the com- ment by Price, Doing Justice to Corrections? Prisoners, Parolees and the Canadian Courts (1977) 3 Queen’s L.J 214.

1 Compare Lazarov v. Secretary of State [1973] F.C. 927 (C.A.) and Prata

v. M.M.L [1976] 1 S.C.R. 376.

13Re Copeland & McDonald [1978] 2 F.C. 815 (T.D.), and the article by Macdonald, The Commission of Inquiry in the Perspective of Administrative Law (1980) 18 Alta L. Rev. No. 3 (forthcoming).

procedures were followed, yet one could claim that procedural defects afflicted the manner in which decisions were taken. The aggrieved parties did not argue that decisions were substantively ultra vires, but that the processes of decision were inappropriate to the decision at hand. Hence, in cases involving the allegation of procedural impropriety, the usual rationale for permitting indivi- duals to seek judicial review, which is to supervise the legality of specific administrative acts so as to redress legitimate grievances when necessary, is generally no more cogent than the subsidiary rationale, that is, to review the structures and processes employed by statutory decision-makers to ensure that agency policy is de- veloped in an orderly and reasonable fashion.

A second distinctive characteristic of implied procedural review may be described as its integrative function. Review on grounds of jurisdiction functions principally in the same manner as an appeal: it protects individuals from unjustified interference and reproaches pretenders to power. Jurisdictional review also provides a second, but more limited, opportunity for dissatisfied persons to advance substantive claims. By contrast, procedural review does not check power, but structures its exercise: it aids in redefining ad- ministrative decision-making in conformity with traditional con- cepts of judicial decision-making. Administration may be charac- terized as the management of specified tasks and problems in order to achieve a determined policy; legal rules of jurisdiction and pro- cedure only limit the framework within which activity is under- taken, and are peripheral concerns of the bureaucrat. To the judge or lawyer, however, questions of policy are peripheral; ambivalent to the needs and constraints of bureaucracy, the Bench and Bar tend to be preoccupied with the outer limits of administrative power and decision-making. 4

Recourse to implied procedural review may thus harmonize major decision-making institutions of government: bureaucratic attention can be directed to means as well as ends, while judicial attention must be directed to ends as well as means. Just as judges must be sensitive to problems of administration when they act as personae designatae under various statutes, or when they are called upon to monitor complex injunctive decrees, the bureaucracy must concern itself with questions of legality if it is subject to review for unfairness in the exercise of its powers of decision. Of course, the, benefits of procedural review will only be realized if the re-

‘ 4Wilson, “Discretion” in the Analysis of Administrative Process (1972) 10

Osgoode Hall L.J 117, 133-9 gives an excellent summary of this distinction.

viewing agency is aware of institutional limitations within which bureaucracies must function.15

Implied due process review possesses a third main feature, namely, that it serves the political function of enfranchisement. While judicial review on jurisdictional grounds is concerned with protection of the substantive rights of those who are party to a decisional process, procedural review is by its nature directed to guaranteeing the effective participation of persons likely to be affected by administrative decisions. In one sense, an essential element of freedom is “the opportunity to participate in decision- making processes”.Y’ When judicial review is sought on procedural grounds, the applicant is in fact claiming to be enfranchised; the argument advanced is not that a decision was itself unlawful, but that one has a right to participate in a certain manner in that decision.

From this perspective, questions of procedural fairness and standing are linked: the latter regulates claims that the value one personifies ought to be within the contemplation of the decision- maker, and hence one ought to be permitted to challenge a deci- sion; 17 the former assumes the function of structuring, in individual cases, the nature of the participation which the law of standing ensures. Procedural review consequently serves an important pur- pose in constitutional theory, that is, to stimulate and guarantee creative and meaningful democratic participation in administrative government. While ultra vires review protects fundamental concepts of legality in any system of law, procedural review enshrines a theory of participation in political institutions which is peculiar to liberal democratic systems.18

Thus, implied procedural review constitutes a distinctive aspect of judicial review of administrative action. For the bureaucratic decision-maker being reviewed, it can be more instructive than ultra vires review. If prospective, directed to institutional difficul-

‘5 Arthurs, supra, note 4, 41-2 is skeptical of the judiciairy’s capacity to exploit the integrative possibilities of review. See also Wexler, Non- judicial Decision-making (1975) 1GFuller, Freedom as a Problem of Allocating Choice (1968) 112 Proc. Am.

13 Osgoode Hall LJ. 841.

Phil. Soc’y 101, 103.

Identity: The Coming of Age of Public Law (1978).

11This metaphorical elaboration of standing is taken from Vining, Legal ‘ 8 See Rostow, The Democratic Character of Judicial Review

(1952) 66 Harv. L. Rev. 193; cf. Mace, The Anti-Democratic Character of Judicial Review (1972) 60 Cal. L. Rev. 1140. Both these articles examine constitutional judicial review in the United States, but their respective theses may be applied to administrative judicial review in Canada.

ties, and structured so as to provide guidelines for future conduct, it may improve the processes of public administration. From the standpoint of the reviewing agency, implied due process review may be a more effective integrative tool than jurisdictional review. Since the special concerns and abilities of legal decision-makers are often procedural, it permits the reviewing agency to express these con- cerns without having to impugn substantive agency policy. From the perspective of the person seeking review, procedural control fulfils a more fundamental political function than ultra vires review. Constitutional principles such as the rule of law are most meaningful in contexts where the right to participate in government is guaranteed; procedural review is directed towards evaluating the nature and conditions of participation accorded to individual citizens.

These three features confirm in principle the desirability of exposing all acts of statutory decision-makers to implied due pro- cess supervision by courts. Although such a perspective is attractive, the benefits achieved must be weighed against the negative aspects of increased review. The late Professor Abel enumerated several of these, including problems relating to status, ripeness, delay, cost, cognitive dissonance and unpredictability. 19 Consequently, an evalua- tion of the desirability of adopting the fairness concept compels the following specific queries: at whose behest, at what time, by whom, in what format and on what grounds should procedural review be permitted? These questions may be restated in three general themes:

is a law of judicial procedural review to be encouraged? is review on procedural grounds most effective when it involves the elaboration and implementation of a structure of rules, or when it results in the creation of something akin to a role morality? should an adversarial, adjudicative paradigm, as opposed to a con- sensual, mediational model of decision, be adopted as the structure for review?

B. The agency of procedural review

Normally, analyses of the review of administrative action do not focus on what agency is the most appropriate body to undertake such review; in fact, the very term “judicial review” seems to preclude this discussion. But in view of the distinctive characteris- tics of procedural review, and the fact that traditional rule-of-law arguments supporting review on jurisdictional grounds are not

19 Abel, Appeals Against Administrative Decisions (1962) 5 Can. Pub. Admin.

65, passim.

directly applicable to implied due process supervision, it is appro- priate to consider whether judicial review is the most desirable mechanism for controlling or superintending decision-making pro- cedures. There are two separate facets to this inquiry: first, do the institutional constraints of judicial review compromise the utility of due process control, and, second, are legally trained individuals who hold judicial appointments necessarily the best equipped to effect the guidance contemplated by implied procedural control?

The institution of judicial review is often confused with the appellate function of courts. Even judges and lawyers who can list salient differences between the two mechanisms often permit the assumptions of one judicial function to permeate others.2 In prin- ciple, a motion for judicial review involves the allegation of a lack of jurisdiction (error of law on the face of the record excepted), which is to say that it involves an indirect attack on the substance of decision, through a direct challenge to the power of the decision- maker to act as he did. Unlike appeals, review implies that for some formal reason to decide, not that his decision was wrong on its merits?’

the decision-maker had no authority

While the blurring of the distinction between appellate and review functions may not be totally inappropriate in cases involving formal ultra vires review,2 2 it is nefarious in cases of implied pro- cedural review. In the latter instances the original decision-maker will invariably be faced again with the same issue, and the review- ing agency must therefore be prepared to provide guidelines as to the maimer of decision-making that can be applied consistently and impartially. Hence the remedial assumptions underlying judicial appellate review do not necessarily apply to implied due process review.

20See P~pin & Ouellette, Principes de contentieux administratif (1979), 338-44 for a brief summary of the major legal differences between statutory appeals and judicial review in administrative law.

21It is not being suggested that certain decisions (especially those in- volving so-called abuses of discretionary power) do not reflect some degree of confusion of jurisdiction and merits. See, e.g., Metropolitan Life Insurance Co. v. International Union of Operating Engineers [1970] S.C.R. 425. Never- theless, there is a theoretical difference between appeals and review which should be maintained if the legal function of each is to be preserved.

22In both cases the original decision-maker is permanently disseized of the dispute, and in both cases a substantive determination is being made. Review for abuse of discretion is a hybrid in that the original decision- maker may continue to have jurisdiction to decide even after his first determination is annulled. Yet this is similar to an appellate court referring a matter back to a trial court for disposition.

Moreover, there are several reasons why vesting review juris- diction in the courts may not be a preferable solution to the problem of which agency should control breaches of procedural propriety on implied grounds. First, implying procedural formalities is an essentially legislative rather than adjudicative activity. The failure of courts to develop a test for determining when a hearing is re- quired attests to this fact. Much of the moderate critique of judicial review on procedural grounds has centered on the fact that un- warranted effort is devoted to the classification of functions, rather than on developing guidelines relating to the situations where the right to a hearing will be implied.2 3 As a result, rarely do review decisions offer criteria for assessing specific procedural formalities. Because judicial review on implied procedural grounds occurs in the context of ordinary judicial proceedings, it necessarily shares the retrospective characteristics of all adjudication upon questions where no fixed standards are present. 4

A second deficiency in judicial review can be traced to the fact that it is seen primarily as litigational and remedial. Because of this orientation, the specific grounds on which review is granted are usually stated as general principles, but not principles that are readily understood by non-lawyers. A failure to relate the procedural requirements being imposed to the dynamics of the decision-making process under review makes extrapolation of these requirements to other contexts almost impossible. Hence, one may find an allegation that the wrong evidentiary standard was applied, but no guidance as to when one or another standard will be appropriate. Similarly, with respect to judicial notice, usually little elaboration is provided as to what does or does not fall within the tribunal’s specialized knowledge, and why. Accordingly, while judicial review judgements may explain why certain procedures are inappropriate, because they are written for lawyers, they rarely provide the same insight for the statutory decision-makers who are expected to abide by them.

A third characteristic of procedural review by courts which is open to criticism is that control on due process grounds is effected by holding the tribunal’s conduct up to a standard, ascer- taining that the standard has not been met, and annulling the re-

23 See, e.g., Reid & David, Administrative Law and Practice, 2d ed. (1978),

chs. 1 and 4.

24 For an attempted justification of such an adjudicative model in the common law, see Fuller, Anatomy of the Law (1968), Pt II. From Fuller’s comments it is clear that implied procedural review falls into the category of decisions having the strongest retrospective flavour.

suiting decision. But, implied due process review is founded not so much on a framework of rules as on an underlying paradigm of decision-making which colours the application of the rules by which impropriety is gauged. When a reviewing court asserts that a lawyer should have been present, or that a hearing should not have been held in camera, it is tempting to view such a decision as being derived from the procedural requirements associated with ordinary civil litigation. Yet neither of these two requirements is commonly found in judicature acts or rules of practice. In effect, the court’s ability to individuate such requirements derives from its understanding of adversarial adjudication as an operative para- digm. Nevertheless, judicial review judgements usually state that some procedural requirement has been breached; rarely do they concentrate on exploring and illustrating the decision-making struc- ture which underlies the requirement being imposed.

An evaluation of which agency should be vested with powers of review on implied procedural grounds also requires an investigation of the aptitudes of the individuals who staff the reviewing body. One must ask whether the priorities and perspectives of the legally trained militate against the development of procedural review across the wide range of functions contemplated by the fairness doctrine s 5 From the beginning it must be remembered that not every exercise of state power is arbitrary, unjust, discriminatory or unreasonable. Poor decisions are as likely to result from under- staffing, overwork, lack of training, and other managerial difficul- ties, all of which presuppose good faith on the part of the decision-maker. However, many lawyers wish to erect elaborate legal controls over the exercise of public power because they fear any exercise of administrative discretion. From this perspective even the possibility of unrestricted exercises of state power is a serious abuse of civil liberties. In commenting on the McRuer Report, Willis noted:

We are told a great deal about the dreadful things that, as the law now stands, civil servants might do to the citizen but are given no actual instances of them actually having done so 2 6

This is to say that the legally trained desire to structure narrowly

25 See Hehner, The Public Servant and the Legalistic Mentality (1970) 13 Can. Pub. Admin. 324. I am not suggesting in the following paragraphs that the legalistic perspective is inappropriate in general: these comments are directed only to the suitability of such an approach in the sphere of implied procedural review.

26Willis, The McRuer Report: Lawyer’s Values and Civil Servant’s Values

(1968) 18 U.T.LJ. 351, 352.

the range of statutory discretions granted to “arbitrary” adminis- trators.21

Individuals who are legally trained tend to be pre-occupied with the adversarial adjucative model of decision-making. The lawyer not only claims that third-party review is a necessary component of a legal system, but he asserts that only control by judicial institutions is a guarantee of the reviewing agency’s in- dependence. The adversary model of adjudication is, however, not a decisional structure well suited to the development of procedural norms: the psychology of confrontation, delay and “winner-take- all” inherent in this system should have no place in a procedural review process. Due process supervision before a tribunal whose procedures are adversarial and adjudicative rests on the assumption that one can find a permanency and immutability of structures and standards, as well as a fixed criterion by which the circumstances of their invocation can be determined. Yet this assumption cannot be sustained, as the recent history of the classification of function exercise has revealed.

One may identify another aspect of the lawyer’s perspective. In reference to the non-adjudicative model of the Conseil d’Etat, Willis said that the McRuer Commission rejected it simply because it was a

“strange new thing”; … the Commission [was preoccupied] with pro- tecting individual rights, and the [influence of] the traditions of the legal profession. 28

In other words, Willis recognized that the greatest impediment to the adoption of such a structure lay in the attitudes of lawyers to processes of the law, the very processes which are themselves un- suited to procedural due process supervision. The legal profession is particularly concerned with tradition and precedent, with form- alism and settled ways of acting. Undoubtedly, the development of new criteria of procedural fairness for non-adjudicative pro- cesses puts a premium on inventiveness, flexibility and experimen- tation.

This brief consideration of certain institutional deficiencies of judicial review on grounds of implied due process requirements, as well as of the intellectual perspectives of the legally trained,

27Such a view is paradoxical, given the acceptance of wide

judicial discretion in evidentiary matters, causation, division of family assets, de- pendent’s relief, injunctions, specific performance, and so on. One may only conclude that it is not discretion which is the object of apprehension, but non-judicial discretion.

28Willis, Foreign Borrowings (1970) 20 U.T.LJ. 274, 279.

suggests that opponents of the judicialization of administrative procedures are advancing a more subtle critique than is usually recognized. The argument is not simply one of parliamentary supre- macy, or even that the administrative process is different from the judicial process. Rather, commentators claim that the institution of judicial review is inappropriate both because it is judicial and because it is review: the legally trained tend to assume the superiori- ty of the common-law adjudicative process, including an emphasis on rules and the adversary system; the nature of review in judicial institutions is remedial, censorial and oriented principally to the invocation of rules. As a consequence one may conclude that the special character of implied review suggests a reconsideration of both the procedures of, and the forum in which, due process super- vision is effected.

C. Rules and roles in implied procedural review

A second question must be addressed before a theory of pro- cedural review can be elaborated. Are the benefits of implied review guaranteed only through the adoption of a framework of rules, or is it also necessary that review have an educational component for decision-makers? This, of course, raises one of the fundamental issues of legal philosophy: to what extent is human conduct governable by rules, and to what extent can rules provide a structure within which responsible decision-making can take place?

As legal thought and practice in Canada are generally positivistic in orientation, these questions may be otiose. Since rules are seen by positivists as self-executing, it follows that human conduct not only can, but can most efficaciously, be subjected to governance by rules. The existence of a legal rule, not its application, is paramount, and the task of deciding when the legal rule is applicable becomes quasi-automatic. Who is deciding, consequently, is of minor signifi- cance in the process of decision-making; moreover, the interpreta- tion and application of law are seen as involving no intellectual process which is external to the language of the legal rule itself.9 Yet the positivistic view of legal decision-making is being chal- lenged. First, lawyers are coming to believe that rules can operate only as guides to decision. A consequence of the latent ambiguity of language is that both the meaning of a rule and its practical applica-

29 Although this caricature of the positivist position is presented without subtlety, it does reflect the main tenets of this school of legal philosophy. For the most coherent treatment see Hart, The Concept of Law (1961), chs. 6-9. A more detailed critique than that presented below may be found in Wexler, Discretion: The Unacknowledged Side of Law (1975) 25 U.T.LJ. 120.

tion in a concrete case are the product of judgement on the part of decision-makers. Even in the presence of a relatively straight- forward linguistic formulation of a legal rule, a decision-maker must himself become implicated in the process of decision.30 Lawyers and judges now acknowledge that legal rules operate in a broader context. Not only do other normative systems condition the meaning of legal rules, but the common lawyer’s concept of a legal rule is a posteriori, in that it is descriptive of a past decision or series of past decisions, and only secondarily prescriptive.31 A final attack on the positivist model is that what is truly distinctive about the legal system is not the structure and contents of its rules, but the expectations and assumptions shared by participants com- mitted to the legal process. It is argued that what permits lawyers to take various human situations, reformulate these into an issue which can be disputed, argue these with conviction before a judge, and understand a decision is not a system of legal rules but rather the learned process of thinking like a lawyer.32

The implications of this alternative

theoretical attitude for implied procedural review are quite significant, so far as they show that due process rules for decision-makers will not alone promote procedural fairness. First, these rules must be capable of integra- tion into other normative systems affecting the decision-maker; second, they must cohere within a system of beliefs about decision- making which is capable of explanation by the reviewing agency; finally, the rules set out must be addressed to the kinds of per- ceptions a statutory decision-maker is likely to share. In other words, procedural review must consist of more than the establish- ment of rules to be followed by administrative decision-makers; it must perform an educative function, encouraging the development of certain paradigms of decision and engendering commitment to them.

The most common process by which such commitments are inculcated is through what sociologists call a “role morality”. Lawyers and other professionals often fail to appreciate how much of their conduct is conditioned by attitudes, approaches and pers- pectives, rather than rules. Confronted with a piece of legislation or the judgement of a court, lawyers react differently from most

30 See Fuller, Positivism and Fidelity to Law – A Reply to Professor Hart

(1958) 71 Harv. L. Rev. 630, 661-9.

3′ See, e.g., Harari, The Place of Negligence in the Law of Torts (1962), 1-18; Fuller, “Some Unexplored Social Dimensions of the Law” in Sutherland, The Path of the Law from 1967 (1968), 57.

32 See Shklar, Legalism (1964), 1-18.

citizens, so far as their training leads them to see certain relation- ships, and not others, to read limitations into certain terms, and not into others, and to formulate problems in particular ways. Legal training usually permits lawyers to interpret written rules coherent- ly: their ability to work with a system of rules derives not so much from the rules themselves as from adopted concepts of role.33 It follows that when an application for judicial review founded on implied procedural grounds results in a general rule respecting appropriate procedures, this rule has a meaning for lawyers which may not be grasped by other statutory decision-makers. Procedural rules about adjudication, developed and promulgated by experienced adjudicators, will only have an impact in the restructuring of decision-making when they are directed to those who are familiar with the idea of procedural rules and with the basic assumptions of adjudication. In any other context they will be much less meaningful because those for whom they are intended will not share the role morality necessary for understanding and implement- ing them. As Felix Cohen once stated:

The ancient wisdom of our common law recognizes that men are bound to differ in their views of fact and law, not because some are honest and others dishonest, but because each of us operates in a value-charged field which gives shape and colour to whatever we see.34 While it is clear that the simple invocation of rules may in the short term improve the procedural fairness of all administrative decision-making (especially where the process under review is ad- judicative in nature), the long-range effectiveness of due process supervision is contingent on two other factors: any rules promulgat- ed must be capable of integration into an appropriate role morality which can be understood by the administrative decision-maker, and the reviewing agency must attempt to involve the decision- maker under review in the creation of this role morality.

D. Adversarial adjudication and implied procedural review

In an earlier section, it was suggested that judicial review on due process grounds might be inappropriate, partly because the forum of review was adversarial in nature. In this section, another aspect of judicial review will be addressed, namely, its potentially limiting effect on the creation and invocation of non-adjudicative paradigms of administrative decision-making. A further question to be addressed in developing a theory of procedural review is thus whether all statutory processes should be evaluated against a back-

33Bishin & Stone, Law, Language and Ethics (1972), ch. 13. 3 Cohen, Field Theory and Judicial Logic (1959) 59 Yale LJ. 238, 242.

drop of adjudication, or whether a variety of decisional paradigms should be created to reflect the procedures by which administra- tors effect public policy.

It is one of the distinctive characteristics of the common law that almost all decisional processes that involve the judiciary are adjudicative. Of course, the promulgation of rules of practice in- volves the exercise of legislative powers; the assignment of judges to certain cases is an administrative act; proceedings in contempt are essentially inquisitorial; reference cases are recommendatory and certain parens patriae procedures are mediational; but the bulk of judicial work is adjudicative. The functions of statutory delegates are more diverse, both in theory and practice. Conse- quently, one may ask whether the paradigm of adversarial adjudica- tion should set the framework for rules of fair procedure in non- adjudicative contexts.

A first step is to consider the concept of adjudication itself. Lawyers can readily identify its major elements. Over the past quarter-century perhaps the most sophisticated work in this area has been that of Lon Fuller.35 He claims that adjudication is a dis- tinctive form of social ordering whose identifying characteristic may be found in the mode of participation granted to affected parties. While others have suggested certain refinements to this thesis, 36 it is indisputable that adjudication “confers on the affected party a peculiar form of participation in the decision, that of presenting proofs and reasoned arguments for a decision in his favour”. 37 From this claim, three underlying norms of adjudication may be derived:

the adjudicator should attend to what the parties have to say; the adjudicator should explain his decision in a manner provides a substantive reply to what the parties have to say; the decision should be strongly responsive to the parties’ proofs and arguments in the sense that it should proceed from and be contingent with those proofs and arguments.3 8

5See Fuller, Adjudication and the Rule of Law (1960) 54 Proc. Am. Soc’y Int’l L. 1; Collective Bargaining and the Arbitrator [1963] Wis. L. Rev. 3; The Forms and Limits of Adjudication (1978) 92 Harv. L. Rev. 353. 36E.g., Eisenberg, Participation, Responsiveness and the Consultative Process (1978) 92 Harv. L. Rev. 410 suggests that one must also consider the degree to which the decision-maker must respond to the arguments of litigants.

37Fuller, The Forms and Limits of Adjudication, supra, note 35, 364. ‘i 3 Eisenberg, supra, note 36, 411-2. See also Summers, Two Types of Substantive Reasons: the Core of a Theory of Common-law Justification (1978) 63 Cornell L. Rev. 707.

One may then derive all the particularized rules associated with judicial proceedings and relate them to the goals of ensuring attention, explanation and strong responsiveness, which preserve the integrity of participation in the process of adjudication. For example, rules respecting bias and openness enhance participation; those respecting notice ensure that such an opportunity genuinely exists; those relating to evidence, cross-examination, counsel and transcripts define the form and content of participation; those touching reasons and appeals guarantee responsiveness to argu- ment.39 Quite evidently, an understanding of the decisional process of adjudication permits the derivation of particular rules, their invocation in particular situations, and the appreciation of why they are essential to procedural due process. 40

Each of these specific procedural rules has no intrinsic validity, except with respect to the decisional paradigm which requires its

39A list of subjects normally seen as characteristic of adjudicative due process follows. It is derived from Levinson, Elements of the Administrative Process (1977) 26 Am. U. L. Rev. 872, 932-3, n. 336.

4OThis understanding also contributes to designing mixed and parasitic forms of adjudication (see Fuller, The Forms and Limits of Adjudication, supra, note 35, 405-9) as well as to distinguishing substantially similar processes (see Eisenberg, supra, note 36, 414-23). It must be remembered that even courts do not engage in one form of adjudication. Cf. the processes of small claims courts, jury trials, preliminary inquiries, appeals, voir dires, motions and bankruptcy petitions.

rules of evidence

access to adverse evidence

formal notice remands and adjournment

(i) preliminary inquiries and discovery (ii) preliminary determinations and settlements (iii) (iv) (v) subpoena for witnesses (vi) production of documents (vii) (viii) pleadings (ix) (x) cross-examination (xi) (xii) access to counsel (xiii) (xiv) (xv) he who decides must hear (xvi) (xvii) reasons xviii) open proceedings (xix) public access (xx) publication of reasons (xxi) (xxii) appeal

interlocutory motions impartial decision-nmaker

record and transcripts

reconsiderations

application. In other words, the requirement of notice or of cross- examination is not prerequisite to procedurally fair decision-making. While these may be absolute requirements for fair adjudication, their invocation in another decisional process should depend on whether they preserve the integrity of that process. Procedural fairness across the range of administrative activity therefore does not simply involve the application of norms appropriate to a relaxed or imperfect form of adjudication; it requires the development of independent paradigms and normative criteria for each distinctive function of administration. Consequently, each of the diverse exer- cises of state power must be characterized (at least in a rudi- mentary fashion) according to the process of social ordering it exemplifies.

Traditionally, for the purposes of implied due process super- vision, administrative decision-making has been characterized as legislative, judicial or (residually) administrative. Moreover, the concept of “policy” has been a principal criterion for distinguishing when natural justice would lie and when decisions would be im- mune from procedural supervision: often a structurally adjudicative determination would be held not to give rise to a duty to act judicially where policy questions were significant. Such situations were identified sometimes by reference to the decisional agency (e.g., the Minister or the Governor-in-Council), sometimes by re- ference to the fact that the problem to be solved involved the manipulation of interdependent interests in order to achieve an optimal solution (e.g., the allocation of television channels),41 and sometimes by acknowledging that it may be almost impossible to order the various criteria which should bear on a decision or to identify the weight to be attached to each standard of decision invoked (e.g., the granting of political asylum or parole) .42 What distinguishes these situations from classical adjudication is the absence of a requirement that decisions be strongly responsive to arguments advanced, not the fact that participation itself is in- appropriate; that is, there are fewer constraints placed on the factors a decision-maker may invoke to justify his conclusions. One may conclude therefore that certain purely administrative functions bear close resemblance to adjudication and involve a process which may be characterized as consultative.

But not all non-judicial statutory functions are similar. One can identify salient differences between the functions of legislating,

41See Fuller, The Forms and Limits of Adjudication, supra, note 35, 405

42 See Eisenberg, supra, note 36, 414 et seq.

landowning, purchasing supplies and services, regulating, prosecut- ing, investigating, taxing, granting exemptions or dispensations – differences which should lead to significant variations in the pro- cedures by which such tasks are performed and the participation which is afforded to affected parties. Of course, it should not be assumed that each different function performed by a statutory decision-maker involves a distinct procedural structure. In fact, it has been argued persuasively that all possible structures and pro- cesses for rational decision-making can be grouped into nine major categories: custom, officially declared law, adjudication, voting, managerial direction, contract, mediation, property and deliberate resort to chance.43 Each of these, it is suggested, may have several variants, yet each possesses distinctive characteristics, which in turn bear on the participation to be afforded to parties affected by decision, and the institutional duties of decision-makers. For ex- ample, what has been characterized as the consultative process is not a parasitic form of adjudication. It is a distinctive social-order- ing process with procedural features that must reflect its internal integrity. Consequently, in order to determine the precise require- ments of procedural fairness, it is necessary to work out what would be an appropriate paradigm for each possible decisional process. Rather than ask what aspects of adjudicative procedures can be grafted onto this decisional process, reviewing tribunals must ask: what is the nature of the process here undertaken, what mode of participation by affected parties is envisioned by such a decisional process, and what specific procedural guidelines are necessary to ensure the efficacy of that participation and the in- tegrity of the process under review? Fuller has suggested some answers to these questions in certain situations. For example, if contract is the relevant decisional process, he believes that negotia- tion is the appropriate mode of participation; in elections he asserts that participation is effected by voting.44 But a better appreciation of the importance of developing paradigms can be gained by taking one such process and examining in detail various aspects of parti- cipation.

43Fuller & Eisenberg, Basic Contract Law, 3d ed. (1972), 89 et seq. 44 Fuller, The Forms and Limits of Adjudication, supra, note 35, 363. The theme is also elaborated in Fuller, Mediation: its Forms and Functions (1971) 44 S. Cal. L. Rev. 305 where he discusses mediation. He has also treated contract: Basic Contract Law, supra, note 43; custom: Human Interaction and the Law (1969) 13 Am. J. Juris. 1; legislation: The Morality of Law, 2d ed. (1969); and management: Irrigation and Tyranny (1965) 17 Stan. L. Rev. 1021.

Fuller has considered the paradigm of mediation at great length. He suggests that the central quality of mediation is the “capacity to reorient the parties toward each other, not by im- posing rules on them, but by helping them to achieve a new and shared perception of their relation, a perception that will redirect their attitudes and dispositions toward one another”.4 In other words, mediation presupposes not an impersonal “act-oriented” decisional framework, but a “person-oriented” context and an inter- connection of interests of sufficient intensity to make collaboration a desired goal; it also presupposes the constant readjustment of perpectives, issues and claims. While adjudication may be seen as a formalized and structured form of decision-making, mediation is a comparatively loose decisional paradigm in which neither fact nor norm is capable of definitive proof.

What is the characteristic form of participation and the appro- priate degree of responsiveness which distinguishes mediation? From Fuller’s analysis we might conclude that it is the indirect pre- sentation and reception of alternative formulations of the problem being mediated, that is, a vicarious negotiation of the norms of decision and the applicable facts.4 6 If one accepts this characteriza- tion, certain features of the mediational process which complement this paradigm emerge:

the mediator must listen to and facilitate the presentation of argument between parties; the mediator should explain counter-proposals in a manner that emphasizes commonality; the mediator must maintain sufficient aloofness from the process so as not to prejudge proofs and arguments notwithstanding that he feels one party to be wrong.

Here it is apparent that participation is institutionally guaranteed only as to its existence, not as to its content. In addition, the crite- rion of responsiveness is unspecified: the other party need not respond directly to counter-argument, and the mediator himself is not restricted to presenting or explaining argument as a formal reply to counter-argument. Finally, there are no constraints against the mediator to justify himself because he decides nothing. The decision, if there is one, rests on the consent of affected parties. Hence, while the norms of adjudication emphasize the purely formal aspects of a third-party decisional process, the norms of

45 Fuller, Mediation: its Forms and Functions, supra, note 44, 327. 46 For a slightly different formulation, see Eisenberg, Private Ordering Through Negotiation, Dispute Settlement and Rule-Making (1976) 89 Harv. L. Rev. 637.

mediation highlight the substance of a consensual decisional pro- cess.

What specific rules of fair procedure (analogous to natural justice in adjudication) are appropriate to mediation? What rules ensure the integrity of the participation and responsiveness ne- cessary to mediation? Some of these may be: notice, adjournment, assistance of counsel, private proceedings, opportunity to present argument, access to counter-proposals, impartial mediator, equal access to mediator, and opportunity for direct negotiation. Of course, many of these items appear on a list of rules of fair pro- cedure appropriate to adjudication. But, given the distinctive character of mediation, it would be incorrect to view this process as an adaptation of classical adjudication. While several procedural features of mediation and adjudication may be similar, their con- ditions of application, as well as their specific impact in concrete cases, may vary greatly. As we have seen, it is the paradigm, not the specific rule, which constitutes the essence of procedural fair- ness.

As the above paragraphs have shown in a summary fashion, the diversity of functions performed by administrative decision- makers has two significant consequences for a theory of procedural fairness: not only must diverse decision-making paradigms, each possessed of its own institutional integrity, be adopted, but the specific normative prescriptions which they imply must be evaluat- ed against that paradigm. Adversarial adjudication is but one of these possible models. Simply because specific procedural require- ments which are similar to those of adjudication flow from a given process is no reason to assume that that process should be subject to a participation/responsiveness paradigm of adjudication or quasi-adjudication.4 7

E. Conclusion

As courts begin to realize the potential scope of the fairness doctrine, they tend to retreat from a full embrace of its implica- tions. This reticence to assume an activist posture of implied super- vision across all decision-making functions is direct evidence of

47 Eisenberg, supra, note 36, 426-32 addresses this point. It is not here being suggested that each of the nine principles are of equal importance. By far the most common will be third-party decision processes such as adjudication, officially declared law and managerial direction. It is precisely these three processes which are most similar, and hence one can appreciate why certain fairness judgements are characterized as “watered-down” natural justice.

what Loughlin calls the crisis in administrative law theory. Like all reformations in public law, fairness has engendered a great deal of uncertainty as courts slowly cast off the incidents, restric- tions and formalities of the discarded theory. Certain developments are immediately foreseeable as the theory of implied procedural review again breaks free of the theory of jurisdiction to which courts and writers have attempted to tie it during the past century. In this liberating process the distinctive character of implied due process supervision will emerge, and three important consequences will follow. First, it will be noticed that, despite their historical concern with matters of fair procedure, lawyers and judges operat- ing within the adversarial system of judicial review may not be appropriate guarantors of procedural fairness in administrative law matters. Second, the theory of implied review will break free of positivistic constraints, and new jurisprudential currents will produce a shift in focus of procedural review away from a unique concern with the rules of fair procedure towards a general concern with the institutions of decision and the role morality of decision- makers who must follow such rules. Finally, as more administrative processes are challenged on applications for procedural review, the diversity and distinctiveness of statutory functions so challeng- ed will impress on reviewing tribunals that, if the rules of proce- dural fairness are derived solely from a model of adversarial ad- judication, the institutionalization of fair procedures for all func- tions is bound to fail.

Nevertheless, a recognition that these three elements’of implied due process review must be at the foundation of a post-Nicholson approach to fairness will not itself resolve the problems which this new doctrine is likely to create. Nor will it lead to a law of pro- cedural review which meets the expectation of various proponents of fairness. In the absence of an institutional model which will en- hance implied procedural review, yet not impair the efficacy of administration, the reformation initiated by Nicholson will be of short duration.

II. An institutional model of implied procedural review

To this point in our inquiry various implications of the doctrine of procedural fairness in administrative law have been considered. A review of the historical and intellectual justifications for due process supervision has demonstrated that implied procedural review cannot be justified by appeal to the principles of jurisdic- tional judicial review. Tracing in detail the possible impact of this new theory in diverse instances of delegated decision-making, and

comparing it with other developments in the field of due process review, revealed the extensive scope of the doctrine. Isolation of the the salient features of procedural supervision permitted derivation of attributes which any comprehensive theory of implied is now possible to deduce procedural review must possess. It rudimentary elements of an institutional model of procedural review and explore the implicit characteristics thereof.

A coherent framework for implied due process supervision of all delegated decision-making functions must acknowledge six prin- ciples. First, given the principal philosophical justifications for pro- cedural review, both the structure and composition of the review- ing agency, as well as the paradigm and norms of review, must have a consensual basis. Second, in view of the variety of administra- tive decision-making bodies, statutory decisional structures and bureaucratic functions performed within these structures, a mono- lithic structure of implied review would be inappropriate. Third, due to the difficulties of subjecting human conduct to written rules, procedural review must consist of an implied element. Fourth, the underlying goals of procedural review mean that the judicial process of adversarial adjudication is probably unsuited to this task. Fifth, given the basic nature of all human decision- making, procedural review should not focus exclusively on the promulgation of a system of rules. Sixth, because administrative functions are so diverse, procedural review can only be meaning- ful when based on a decision-making paradigm compatible with the process under scrutiny. In other words, the elucidation of a model of implied procedural review which fully exploits the avenues opened up by the Nicholson case requires nothing less then a funda- mental re-examination of the premises of such review. In the following pages we shall propose a model which respects these six principles, and then review it in light of criticisms that are likely to be directed against it.

A. The model in outline

Any complete model of implied procedural review must en- compass four principal elements: the structure of the reviewing agency, its personnel and its powers must be determined; the grounds for and the manner of invoking review must be stipulated; the procedures to be followed by the reviewing panel will require clari- fication; and the focus and purposes of review must be elucidated.

1. The agency of review

The agency of review proposed here would be a multi-member panel staffed by legally trained and non-legally trained personnel. Each member of the panel would be chosen because he is expert in the management of tasks normally performed within one or more of the nine processes of social ordering identified earlier. Hence, the panel would consist of trained and experienced adju- dicators, mediators, electoral experts, negotiators, legislators, persons familiar with management, custom and statistics, and, finally, individuals appreciating the social ordering function of property. In other words, rather than an agency composed entirely of those whose predominant experience and expertise lies in ad- judication, the proposed panel would draw on a diverse group which collectively would have experience and expertise in all principal processes of social ordering in modern Canadian society. Finding those with expertise in mediation, arbitration, negotia- tion, developing legislative guidelines or the operation of custom, would not be a particularly onerous task; within the legal commu- nity itself are experts in each of these processes. Moreover, ex- perienced professionals in the design of elections or in the de- velopment of models that ensure fair results when resort is de- liberately had to chance are also numerous. Of course, many are not likely to be found in the legal community but among sociologists, mathematicians, actuaries and political scientists. An almost inex- haustible pool of those with knowledge about management can be drawn from business or labour. Property as an ordering device presents greater difficulties, although philosophers, economists and lawyers have contributed to our practical appreciation of this con- cept.

A review panel so staffed would consist of those who have studied the theoretical forms and limits of each of these processes of social ordering – processes which are invoked daily in adminis- trative decision-making throughout Canada. Moreover, each would have substantial experience with one of these basic processes, as a participant or decision-maker. Finally, the panel as a whole would not be dominated by the notion that adversarial adjudication is the epitome of procedural fairness for all situations. Hence, the same motives which impel the assignment of particular judges to preside over certain cases, in order to ensure the requisite degree of expertise, can be invoked with respect to this panel at a pro- cedural level.

In so far as other aspects of the review panel are concerned, there is no reason to suppose that appropriate mechanisms, based

on current judicial practice, cannot be adopted. Provisions relating to qualification, nomination, appointment, confirmation, tenure, removal, salary, and training, which today promote the inde- pendence of the judiciary, should be enacted with respect to this tribunal. That is, much of the structure relevant to the constitution of an appellate court may be easily adapted to the new panel. Of course, as is the case with the judicial system, the fundamental guarantee of justice is the selection of the most qualified candidates.

2. Grounds for and manner of invoking review

Given the vast number of procedural disputes which arise in the normal course of administration, some mechanism for structuring the grounds of review, and for formalizing the manner of invoking review, must be developed. There is no reason why initiative in seeking review should not remain in the hands of aggrieved parties. Any inconveniences resulting from the fact that an administrative decision might be open to review on implied procedural grounds48 are more than off-set by the violence to common law principles of legality that would result from removing carriage of a dispute from litigants. Moreover, the courts have developed a sophisticated array of doctrines to control abuses of the judicial review process. Theories of standing, ripeness, exhaustion, primary jurisdiction, laches, mootness, and the like, can still be invoked in order to control frivolous litigation. 9

Not only should initiative in seeking review be left to aggrieved parties,, but so should the precise make-up of the forum of review. Given the unwieldiness of multi-member tribunals, it would be unrealistic to structure the process so that an expert in each of the principal forms of social ordering participates in every applica- tion for review. Rather, each party should be permitted to select one member of the reviewing panel.50 In other words, each disputant

48Though the question of privative clauses is not addressed in this essay, the author sees no reason for excluding access to the review panel. Many of (expertise, efficiency, the traditional finality) are simply inapplicable to review by the proposed tribunal.

justifications for privative clauses

49 On standing, see Vining, supra, note 17, ch. 10; on ripeness, see his article, Direct Judicial Review and the Doctrine of Ripeness in Administrative Law (1971) 69 Mich. L. Rev. 1443.

GOIt is, of course, important to determine who the parties to a dispute are. For example, in certification procedures before a Labour Board are the parties, say, the employer and the Board (or the union and the Board) or the employer and the union? In many cases the precise issue over which unfairness is being alleged will be that of who are properly parties. No attempt will be made to resolve this question here, although, presumably, the principles currently invoked in review proceedings may reflect the difficulties noted with respect to other aspects of procedural review.

would be entitled to require that one member of the tribunal have expertise in a decisional process which the applicant selects. This proposals has two elements which are immediately apparent: first, review would be accomplished by two-man panels, and, second, while the specific members of each panel would be assigned by the secretariat, each party would be permitted to select the decisional paradigm from which that member is drawn. Many advantages for the development of a detailed law of procedural review flow from these characteristics. A two-man format compels the unani- mous disposition of review applicationsY1 It also makes explicit the tacit accommodations which now go for the most part un- noticed in appellate decision-making. Finally, two-man panels are eminently suitable for mediation of competing claims. Since the entire framework of procedural review under this proposed model is intended to be non-adversarial, a three-man panel based on the labour arbitration model would not be an appropriate institutional form

The second aspect of the proposal, selection by each party of the paradigm of review, also offers several advantages. This mechanism permits parties to advance competing perspectives as to the nature of the decisional process. Rather than constraining the participation by affected parties to argument about the applicability of specific rules, this model also permits them to debate the frame- work of decision; this framework is, of course, a principal deter- minant of the procedural rules thought to be appropriate Per- mitting such choice also compels each party to justify why a particular decisional model, or variant thereof, should be preferred. The principal review question becomes explicit, not tacit; one no longer argues for a quasi-judicial function as a means to an end, but on the contrary, the paradigm sought becomes one of the ends of a review proceeding. It is also apparent that paradigm selection by affected parties encourages the sophistication of generalized models of administrative processes for application to specific cases. A more subtle law of procedural fairness will result from tempering decisional paradigms by permutations of panel membership. Rather than a model that compels a single panel, the court, to choose between adjudication or non-adjudication, the proposal would

51 See Llewellyn, The Common Law Tradition (1960), 316-7. 52 See subsection 3, infra, for a discussion of this point. On the adjudicative three-man panels, see Fuller, Collective Bargaining and the

nature of Arbitrator, supra, note 35, 36-42.

53 On the role of paradigms in thought, see Polanyi, Personal Knowledge

(1958), chs. 5-7.

permit as many as forty-five different panels to choose one of nine paradigms; rather than compelling parties to argue a given per- spective before a panel whose presuppositions are only adjudicative, this model encourages the presentation of problems before a panel, at least one member of which is known to have insight and expertise in the decisional process advocated by each party.

With respect to grounds for review, the model contemplates certain deviations from established and recently proposed models. Traditionally, there have been two aspects of procedural review in administrative law, review for procedural ultra vires and implied procedural review. Modem proposals include these two grounds in addition to review for procedural unfairness and for certain abuses of discretion of a procedural nature.5 4 However, the institutional model of review suggested here does not envision all “procedural” is established to consider only implied procedural grounds. It matters, natural justice, fairness and implied limits on discretionary procedures, which operate where legislation is silent or obscure. Formal ultra vires control of administrative procedures would re- main with the courts. Not only would parties to a dispute have the power to choose the nature of the decisional paradigm against which their claim would be evaluated, but they would also have the power, in certain cases, to elect whether to make a statutory procedural claim or an implied procedural claim.

3. The procedures of review

An important corollary of permitting affected parties to parti- cipate in the selection of the grounds of review and the composition of the review panel is their direct involvement in the development of the reviewing agency’s decision. In normal judicial review applica- tions, which, by the fact that they are brought before courts, must proceed on adjudicative assumptions, complaining parties attempt to invoke a normative standard, present facts demonstrating the applicability of the standard, and ask the court to take a censorial decision on whether the standard was attained. The judicial deci- sion is theoretically that of the judge alone and is based on exist- ing standards. However, under the proposed model the procedures of review are non-adjudicative. Since one is disputing implied pro- cedural norms, it is clear that these cannot be antecedent in the sense required by the adjudicative model; and since the facts in issue are fluid and not determinative of the merits, it is difficult

54See Report of the Commonwealth Administrative Review Committee

(1971); Mullan, The Federal Court Act (1978), 61-74.

to see how they could be evaluated by a judge. In such circumstan- ces, a mediational approach to decision must be followed.; . The evaluation of procedural impropriety on implied grounds, therefore, cannot be based on considerations relating to the require- ments of rules: within the confines of statutory powers the deter- mining element cannot be an authoritarian, externally-imposed vision of due process, but must be found in the negotiated consent of those subject to it. It has already been shown that in the absence of procedural standards which flow from legislation, the compo- nents of fair procedure can only be developed by the parties them- selves. A model for reviewing implied procedural requirements should permit parties to engage in a reciprocal adjustment of their procedural expectations. The proposed structure achieves this goal at two levels. First, parties are required through the nomination of one member of the panel to decide what procedural paradigm is most appropriate to the process being reviewed. Second, per- mitting the review panel to participate actively in working out the elements of fair procedure and to share the decisional task with parties will encourage compromise, accommodation and flexibility in expectations.

A mediational approach to review also enhances acceptance, by both parties, of the solution proposed. They are given the oppor- tunity to shape the issue. Both are encouraged to advance argu- ments based on the constraints under which they work, such as time, cost, manpower and case-load. Both are permitted to suggest modifications to proposals of the review panel in order to make the disposition more satisfactory to their individual needs. Finally, a mediational theory of implied procedural review is beneficial for administrative law generally: solutions achieved are likely to be more appropriate because they are directed to specific problems of specific agencies, not to generalizations based on some assumed equivalence of processes across a variety of tribunals and powers. In addition, as the French have demonstrated in many areas of review, mediation removes the censorial focus of decisions that take statutory decision-makers to task, thereby encouraging com- pliance with solutions proposed 6

55See Northrop, The Epistemology of Legal Judgments (1962) Nw. U. L. Rev. 732; Neef & Nagel, The Adversary Nature of the American Legal System from a Historical Perspective (1974) 20 N.Y.L.F. 123, 154-63.

56See Brown & Garner, French Administrative Law, 2d ed.

(1973); cf. Angus, The Individual and the Bureaucrocy: Judicial Review – Do We Need It? (1974) 20 McGill LJ. 177.

4. The focus of review

Because implied procedural review is particularly concerned with institutional failings, rather than with individual deviations from the jurisdiction contemplated by an empowering statute, the focus of review must be essentially prospective.5 In other words, the traditional concept of a bipolar, retrospective and self-contained model of review is not appropriate in these situations. Review must not be simply reproachful: it must be educational. Those who find their determinations subject to review on procedural grounds may be individuals at any level of the bureaucracy; often, it may be an entire process of decision and appeal that is challenged. In such circumstances, review on procedural grounds can be considered successful only if those subject to it actually modify procedures so as to institute fair decisional procedures.

Much recent writing about judicial review does not explicitly acknowledge this factor. In a recent study, Mullan concludes that a reviewing court should have:

(a) a power to set aside (b) a power to refer back for reconsideration (c) a power to prevent an authority from proceeding further (d) a power to compel the making of a decision or order to perform a legal duty, including the following of correct procedures in making a decision

(e) a power to issue a declaration of right, including a declaration with respect to the possibilities in (a) to (d) and referable to all the codified grounds of review.58

Each of. these powers, however, focuses on the traditional adver- sarial model of review and does not allow for the peculiar charac- teristics of implied procedural supervision.

Adopting what Chayes calls the “public law model” of adjudica- tion,59 the focus of review and the powers exercisable should include first the usual power to correct and remit. Second, the review panel must have the power to supervise the implementation of its me- diated decrees. Much like judicial competence in injunctive pro- ceedings in the United States, which presupposes a continuing supervision of the terms of the decree, 60 the review panel must have all necessary power to ensure the efficacy of its order. Third, jurisdiction to investigate and recommend with respect to matters beyond those remitted to it should also be granted. If a particular

L. Rev. 1281, 1281-4.

57 Chayes, The Role of the Judge in Public Law Litigation (1976) 86 Harv. 58 Mullan, supra, note 54, 71. 59 See Chayes, supra, note 57. 60 See Fiss, The Civil Rights Injunction (1978), passim.

[‘Vol. 26

difficulty appears to be symptomatic of a larger problem, the panel should be permitted, on its own initiative, to study the larger problem. Implied procedural review acknowledges that the disputes presented are neither self-contained episodes nor entirely party-con- trolled, and should not be considered as affecting only private rights.6’ Finally, given the significance of role morality in evaluating questions of procedural propriety, the panel must have the power to recommend educational programs that will redress failures in institutional training or practice.62 If due process review is to enhance the development, maintenance and application of sophis- ticated procedures for the exercise of delegated powers, its en- franchising, exemplary and educational functions become para- mount.6 5. Summary

The model proposed is based on the premise that, within the confines of statutory rules, what constitutes fair procedure is a matter of agreement and must rest on a notion of consent. It assumes that, although the specific contents of a fair procedure are variable, this notion will always involve a permutation of basic social-ordering mechanisms. Hence, while adjudication alone is a reductionist paradigm for procedural fairness, there are a limited number of alternatives which, if invoked, would not purchase uniformity at the expense of subtlety. The model also rests on the belief that an adversarial procedure militates against effective development of fair procedural paradigms, and that a mediational theory of review proceedings is more consistent with what is emerg- ing as the public-law model of litigation. 4 Again, it presupposes that prospective review, comprising educational, supervisory and preventative elements should be the goal of procedural supervision. It also requires that parties to an application adopt a posture of other-directedness. Finally, the model assumes that the review panel would be composed of persons experienced in and critical of the forms and limits of various social institutions. The same level of insight which judges express about adjudication must be expected of other panel members in their areas of expertise.

Of course, this model reflects a substantial departure from traditional beliefs about judicial review of administrative action.

61 See Vining, supra, note 17, chs. 9-11. 6 See Wilson, supra, note 14, 125-39. 63See Ryle, “Knowing How and Knowing That” in The Concept of Mind 64But see Thibault & Walker, Procedural Justice: A Psychological Analysis

(1949), 27-49; Holt, How Children Fail (1964), 104-7.

Its premises may appear vulnerable to attack by defenders of the Diceyan concept of the rule of law.6 Yet the difficulties experienced by courts in applying the fairness doctrine should be taken as evidence that administrative law in Canada is on the verge of a fundamental reorientation in which many new proposals for implied review are apt to be considered. Nevertheless, it is certain that this model will be subject to various challenges; to the extent these may be anticipated, they must be addressed.

B. Possible objections to the model

Earlier sections of this essay have been devoted to establishing the validity of the assumptions sustaining the model outlined above. Yet, in themselves, these presuppositions do not justify the specific proposal presented. Moreover, the utility of the model must be argued in both theoretical and practical terms. Since any statutory reform involves substantial change-over costs and engenders resist- ance from those who must make the ‘system work, it must be shown that pragmatic criticisms of the proposal are unfounded. In principle, two basic kinds of counter-argument may be ad- vanced, those relating to fundamental constitutional issues and those relating to difficulties of implementation.

1. Constitutional problems

lawyers will

immediately see

Canadian administrative

two major problems with the proposed model. It will be suggested that a provincially created review panel would be unconstitutional- by virtue of section 96 of the British North America Act, 186766 if its members were provincially appointed;6 or, even if the agency were constitutional, its decisions could not be insulated from judicial review, a needed protection if the panel is to make legally con- clusive determinations. Either of these objections, if valid, would severely compromise the proposal as a model for implied pro- cedural review in Canada.

Recent jurisprudence of the Supreme Court of Canada on the scope of section 96 of the B.N.A. Act gives cause for some concern as to constitutionality. While decisions such as Tomko v. Labour

65 See Arthurs, supra, note 4. 6630 & 31 Vict., c. 3 (U.K.) as am. 67The problem of s. 96 and judicial review was also addressed by the McRuer Royal Commission Inquiry Into Civil Rights (1968-70), 1465-6, which considered the constitutional issue an insurmountable obstacle to the adoption of a Conseil d’Etat model. But see Willis, supra, note 28.

Relations Board (N.S.) , 6 Jones v. Board of Trustees of Edmonton Catholic School District No. 769 and City of Mississauga v. The Regional Municipality of Peel” seem to suggest a more liberal approach to provincial attempts to vest tribunals with a panoply of powers, the important judgement in Farrah v. Attorney-General of the Province of Quebec7′ appears to reflect an opposite trend. In the Jones case, the Court held that the mere “fact that a pro- vincial tribunal is required to exercise a judicial function does not, of itself, involve a conflict with s. 96. ”2 Moreover, in Tomko it stated that “it is not the detached jurisdiction or power alone that is to be considered but rather its setting in the institutional arrange- ments in which it appears and is exercisable under the provincial legislation.”73 In other words, a provincial government may establish a body which performs section 96 functions if these are closely in- tegrated with, incidental to and necessary for the carrying out of valid provincial purposes. But, of course, a review panel of the nature suggested is not part of an integrated institutional arrange- ment touching a bona fide provincial power; it is a quasi-appellate body exercising a general supervisory jurisdiction over the form, not the substance, of administrative decision.

In this context, both Jones and Tomko are of less relevance than Farrah, a judgement which directly involved the constitutionality of a quasi-appellate review body. The import of this latter case is particularly difficult to ascertain, however, because two distinct lines of reasoning won support in the Supreme Court. If one adopts the reasoning of Laskin C.J., it would seem that whenever a province attempts to devolve a purely judicial function on a tri- bunal, divorced from a substantive validating context, section 96 powers are being usurped. The Chief Justice stated:

The difficulty in the present case is that the Transport Tribunal has not been constituted as simply a tribunal of appeal within the administrative structure of the Transport Act, empowered to hear appeals from deci- sions of the Transport Commission and to decide questions of law in the course of a general appellate authority. It is constituted as an appeal agency which, under s. 58(a), is primarily concerned with questions of law.74

68 [1977] 1 S.C.R. 112. 69 [1977] 2 S.C.R. 872. 70 [1979] 2 S.C.R. 244. 71 [1978] 2 S.C.R. 638. See the comment by Ppin, (1978) 38 R. du B. 818; see also Lemieux, Supervisory Judicial Control of Federal and Provincial Public Authorities in Quebec (1979) 17 Osgoode Hall LJ. 133, 146-8.

72 Supra,. note 69, 893. 7 3 Supra, note 68, 120. T4 Supra, note 71, 6434.

From the perspective of the Chief Justice, if questions of implied procedural review determined by the proposed panel are charac- terized as questions of law to be decided by an appellate tribunal, the model may run afoul of section 96 of the B.N.A. Act.

On the other hand, according to Pratte J., the unconstitutionality of the Transport Tribunal at issue in Farrah arose from the fact that it exercises part of the supervisory jurisdiction over questions of law, within or outside jurisdiction, vested exclusively in superior courts. He suggested that non-jurisdictional review may be sup- pressed by an appropriately worded privative clause, but he held that it cannot be transferred to a non-section 96 court:

The net combined effect of s. 58(a) and of the privative clause (ss. 24 and 72 of the Transport Act) is therefore to transfer to the Transport Tribunal part of the inherent supervisory authority that was vested in the Superior Court at the time of Confederation.75

Adopting this reasoning, it would seem that, if implied procedural review is characterized as part of the inherent jurisdiction of the superior court at Confederation, then it cannot be transferred to a non-section 96 body.

How does the proposed review panel square with the reasons for judgement in Farrah? For the Chief Justice, the criterion to be satisfied is whether implied due process questions are questions of law. Throughout his judgement Laskin C.J. refers only to questions of. jurisdiction or of statutory interpretation as questions of law. In fact, his insistence on the importance of the Transport Tribunal’s power to “confirm, vary or quash” a decision on the merits suggests that only statutory provisions are to be considered as law76 Hence, while questions of interpretation arising from statutory procedural provisions may be questions of law, his judgement in Farrah does not directly suggest that issues of implied review constitute questions of law. In other Supreme Court decisions there are sug- gestions that such questions are not questions of law.T7 Never- theless, it is doubtful whether the Court would treat implied review, even in a mediational setting, as a non-section 96 function.7

In so far as the judgement of Pratte J. is concerned, a different problem arises, namely, was implied procedural review inherent in the powers of a superior court at Confederation? Certainly this

15 Ibid., 656. 7G Ibid., 646. This, of course, conflicts with his dissenting opinion in Re

Martineau (No. 1) [1978] 1 S.C.R. 118.

77Re Martineau (No. 1), ibid.; Harelkin v. University of Saskatchewan 78 See particularly the recent Ontario Court of Appeal decision Reference

(1979) 96 D.L.R. (3d) 14 (S.C.C.).

Re Residential Tenancies Act (1979) 26 O.R. (2d) 609, 632-41.

could not have been the case with respect to any non-judicial power, although a more subtle response is necessary with respect to judicial powers. Since Parliament could pre-empt the implied review power of King’s Bench by enacting procedural provisions, it is hard to consider this power as a necessary attribute of a superior court. Traditionally the sine qua non of procedural supervision was a direction from Parliament to act judicially. This could take the form of a right to a hearing, a right to counsel, a right to reasons, or to some other express threshold requirement. Although the content of implied supervision was generally free of legislative control, its existence was contingent on a legislative mandate. Again, however, it is unclear whether these factors are sufficient to indicate that procedural review was not inherent in the sense intended by Mr Justice Pratte.

Thus, the effect of section 96 on the proposed model is far from certain.7 9 It would seem that as long as the review panel neither decides substantive questions of jurisdiction or law, nor decides questions of procedural ultra vires, it may not be found to be exercising a section 96 function; hence, its members may be validly appointed by a province. On the assumption that the pro- posed panel would be considered a section 96 court, the model would nevertheless not fail in so far as federal jurisdiction is concerned, nor would it fail at the provincial level if Law Society statutes were amended so as to permit non-legally trained indi- viduals to be called to the Bar, and if co-operation between the federal and provincial governments as to appointment of these individuals could be assured.

The second constitutional consideration which may scuttle the proposed model relates to whether its decisions may be impressed with the stamp of finality. That is, is it possible to insulate both the decisions of primary tribunals and the decisions of the review panel from ordinary judicial supervision? For, if not, the very problems of adversariness and adjudication to be overcome by creation of such a model will simply manifest themselves one step later in the decisional process.

79 Prediction in this area is almost impossible. In a recent decision, Procureur gdndral du Qudbec v. Crevier [1979] C.A. 333, a 2-1 decision purporting to apply Farrah, the Quebec Court of Appeal found the Tribunal des professions not to be exercising a s. 96 function, even though its constitution, and many of its powers, are almost identical to those of the Transport Tribunal which were at issue in Farrah. Moreover, it should be noted that for Pratte J. the existence of a privative clause (which is part of this proposal as well) rein- forced his view that the Transport Tribunal was exercising s. 96 functions.

With respect to the determinations of primary decision-makers, the problem of insulation from implied procedural control is not of great moment. It has long been acknowledged that implied pro- cedural control plays a suppletive role and hence may be ousted by appropriate statutory language.80 Moreover, recent authority suggests that express prohibitory clauses,8′ as well as the tacit direction resulting from adoption of sophisticated procedural codes 2 may be effective to preclude judicial review on implied due process grounds. Furthermore, primary jurisdiction and exhaus- tion clauses stipulated in favour of second-level administrative tribunals have been judged effective,8 3 and hence might be used to reinforce this protection from immediate judicial review. It follows, therefore, that an appropriately worded privative clause, while not necessarily excluding supervision on grounds of pro- cedural ultra vires, may effectively insulate the processes of primary implied procedural decision-makers grounds.

Protection of the determinations of the review panel is likely to be more difficult. If the tribunal is constituted as a section 96 superior court, this problem would not arise. However, if the tribunal is considered either as a section 96 non-superior court or as an ordinary administrative agency, it is obvious that any of its decisions will be taken in the exercise of a limited statutory juris- diction. In such cases, it seems unlikely that jurisdictional review by a superior court could ever be fully precluded, 4 although infra- jurisdictional errors may be effectively insulated from review. One may conclude therefore that, on any hypothesis, the super- visory power of superior courts over errors of law within juris- diction and implied due process failings of the review panel itself may be precluded; only formal jurisdictional questions would be left open to review.

80 See de Smith, Judicial Review of Administrative Action, 3d ed. (1973), 161

et seq.; Wade, Administrative Law, 4th ed. (1978), 453-6.

81 Re Downing & Graydon, supra, note 1. For a case where implied review

was held to be ousted by contract see Re Proctor, supra, note 1.

82 See, e.g., Furnell v. Whangarei High School Board [1973] A.C. 660 (P.C.);

Wiseman v. Borneman [1971] A.C. 297 (H.L.).

8 3 See, e.g., Hnatchuk v. Workmen’s Compensation Board [1972] 3 W.W.R.

395 (Sask. C.A.).

84 But see Pringle v. Fraser [1972] S.C.R. 821 and Re Woodward Estate [1973] S.C.R. 120 for specialized privative provisions held effective even as against jurisdictional errors. See also Hogg, Is Judicial Review of Administra- tive Action Guaranteed by the B.N.A. Act? (1976) 54 Can. Bar Rev. 716; and Lemieux, supra, note 71, 148-52.

Would this limited review impair the operation of the proposed panel?8 5 There are three reasons for concluding that it would not. In the first place, given the consensual nature of proceedings before the review tribunal, it is unlikely that its determinations would lead to many applications for judicial review. This would be especially so in non-judicial situations, where courts have con- tinued to show a reluctance to find procedural unfairness. Second, since the panel would not make determinations on the merits of a dispute, and since its recommendations will always fall within the interstices of statutory procedures, it is unlikely that formal juris- dictional errors relating to absence, excess or declining of juris- diction would arise. Moreover, by their very nature, the jurisdic- tion and powers of the tribunal would be cast in subjective, general and wide language; this itself should reduce the scope of judicial intervention.86 Finally, in view of judicial treatment of analogous powers in other contexts,87 a deferential approach to determinations of the review panel is not unlikely.

Of the two constitutional objections which critics of the model may advance, the section 96 question is more serious. Problems with respect to privative clauses may be minimized or overcome and, since the concept of judicial review itself is not threatened, one cannot foresee a restrictive approach to the jurisdiction of the review panel. The section 96 issue may, however, significantly im- pede implementation of the scheme. Nevertheless, this obstacle does not arise with respect to any federal tribunal and, as illus- trated, co-operation between the federal and provincial govern. ments can ensure the proposal’s success even at the provincial level. 2. Pragmatic criticisms of the proposed model

The two criticisms of a constitutional nature just reviewed can to the model. Of much

be considered as technical reproaches

85The word “limited”

is used advisedly. Although decisions such as Metropolitan Life Insurance Co. v. Int’l Union of Operating Engineers, supra, note 21, seem to suggest an extensive inventory of jurisdictional errors capable of sustaining review in the face of a privative clause, judicial activism on grounds of abuse of discretion seems to have been on the wane during the past few years, See, e.g., C.U.P.E. Local 963 v. N.B. Liquor Commission [1979] 2 S.C.R. 227. See also Grey, Discretion in Administrative Law (1979) 17 Osgoode Hall L.. 107; Molot, Administrative Discretion and Current Judicial Activism (1979) 11 Ott. L. Rev. 337.

86 For a review of recent Canadian jurisprudence on these indirect privative

provisions see Mullan, Administrative Law, 2d ed. (1979), 222-229.

aTE.g, the Rules Committee under The Statutory Powers Procedure Act,

S.O. 1971, c. 47.

greater concern are substantive, operational critiques. Exploring these will more thoroughly elucidate the proposal. There are five (i) the pro- types of pragmatic criticism which may be advanced: posal is cumbersome and unwieldy; (ii) lawyers are unlikely to (iii) disputes between develop confidence in non-judicial review; citizen and state cannot be mediated since the parties have unequal bargaining power; (iv) establishing an additional review tribunal (v) recruitment of will aggravate jurisdictional complications; tribunal personnel will be extremely difficult. Many of these objec- tions are corollaries to criticisms advanced against the assumptions argued earlier. Nevertheless, each can be answered on a purely pragmatic basis.

Unwieldiness might be alleged on one of two grounds: either the volume of cases will prevent the panel from performing its suggested role, or the number of panel members, and the variety of their backgrounds, will inhibit development of a coherent juris- prudence. The first argument is unfounded, for there is no reason to suppose that the creation of a new review panel will lead to increased applications for judicial review.8 8 Moreover, certain features of the proposal are expressly designed to facilitate the the review tribunal will deal only with disposition of cases: implied due process applications; it will be able to sit in several two-man panels at the same time; and because it will not be making determinations on the merits similar cases often could be heard together. This last point would be most applicable to mass- participation social insurance schemes such as Medicare, Unemploy- ment Insurance, Canada Pension Plan, Workers’ Compensation, and Old Age Security, whenever parties opt for similar panel structures. A final reason for doubting this critique is that the panel could employ traditional mechanisms to regulate its work. Doctrines such as mootness, ripeness, exhaustion, alternative remedy, primary juris- diction and standing can be used, not to frustrate internal agency review, but constructively to improve control of administrative procedures.8 9 Therefore, it is unlikely that the proposal will en- gender so many applications for procedural review that its purposes would be frustrated. Yet, the role proposed for the new tribunal

88See the statistics compiled on the Divisional Court (Ontario) by The Report of the Attorney-General’s Committee on the Appellate Jurisdiction of the Supreme Court of Ontario (1977), 7-11. This report concludes that increased litigation results principally from factors other than the structure of dispute-settling institutions.

89 See the model of the court function proposed by Stone in “Existential Humanism and the Law”, reproduced in Existential Humanistic Psychology (1971).

will mean that each case it hears will require a longer time to settle; for it is an acknowledged benefit of classical adjudication 0 The use of technological that it expedites dispute settlement devices, clerks, research assistants and the like will be necessary to permit the panel to perform its additional functions. Ultimately, however, the management of a burdensome case-load can be ac- complished only by appointing more members to the tribunal. In an era of excessive recourse to institutional mechanisms of dispute- settlement such a necessity cannot be overlooked.01

This solution leads to a discussion of the second aspect of the unwieldiness criticism, that is, the observation that a large, multi- member tribunal inevitably becomes factious and unable to main- tain a coherent review posture. This objection is particularly apt in the case of adjudicative panels, where ideas such as objectivity, stare decisis and certainty are cherished. Yet these have been reveal- ed as illusions, even in the case of purely adjudicative tribunals. Given the underlying structure of the proposed tribunal, these ideas are simply inapplicable: decisions of the tribunal are me- diated; each process of decision is acknowledged as unique; there is no pre-existing law to be applied; the administrative agency under review will ultimately have consented to the solution pro- posed; presumably it will eventually institute fair decisional pro- cess; and, lastly, because the goals of review are not exclusively rule-oriented, it is unlikely that similar cases (as similarity is understood in the doctrine of precedent) will arise. Hence, the objection of unwieldiness, as directed to the tribunal’s juris- prudence, can be met.

A second criticism of the model may be that lawyers will be unable to adjust to non-judicial review. This objection also involves various themes. It could be claimed that lawyers do not trust any decisional body other than a court. While this may be generally true, there are numerous situations where, due to the complexity of the problems involved or the need for expertise, non-judicial decision-making is preferred by lawyers: commercial arbitration, grievance proceedings, and management by a trustee in bankruptcy are only three commonplace examples. If members of the review panel are carefully selected, and if their decisions are subsequently proven apposite, this structure will also attract the commitment of the Bar.

90 See Llewellyn, supra, note 51, 19-50. 91 See Barton, Behind the Legal Explosion (1975) 27 Stan. L. Rev. 567; Carrington, Crowded Dockets and the Court of Appeals (1968-69) 82 Harv. L. Rev. 542.

But the adjustment by lawyers must also be to a process which is non-adjudicative. Because current legal practice occurs almost exclusively before adjudicative panels, this may prove more difficult. Nevertheless, only a small percentage of litigation lawyers are involved in judicial review. Those who are engaged in seeking review of administrative action have already made one adjustment away from the private-law orientation of ordinary practice. Con- sequently, for those who will handle the bulk of the cases before the new tribunal, a further adjustment should not be unmanage- able. Yet the extent to which new models and procedures of review can be successful, in view of the acknowledged conservatism of the legal profession, is of crucial importance, and the difficulties in promoting the review proposal should not be underestimated. 92 A non-adjudicative review panel is also likely to incur criticism that disputes between citizen and state cannot be mediated. This objection is, of course, principally ideological and can be traced to Dicey’s misrepresentation of French droit administratifY93 Dicey felt that administrative justice would prevail only if relations between citizen and state could be converted into a lis inter partes capable of adjudication before the “ordinary courts”. This belief rests, however, on two questionable assumptions: first, that “or- dinary courts” equalize parties and, second, the state possesses superior power in arguing procedural points. To the uninitiated it may appear that procedures before ordinary courts guarantee equal justice for all, yet most lawyers recognize that the traditional model of adjudication enhances the power of the economically stronger party. Factors such as quality of counsel, availability of costly dilatory measures, extensive discovery, possibility of strategic appeals and the like, can only be seen as the prerogative of the wealthier party.94 Dicey’s first assumption that the procedures of adjudication are value-free cannot be sustained on available evidence.

As for Dicey’s conclusion that the state possesses superior power in procedural matters, one must ask whether a mediational model allows the same abuses as adjudication. May it not be the case that the very conversion of public-law disputes to a format

92For a more pessimistic view of the potential for reform see Mullan, Reform of Judicial Review – Method or Madness? (1975) 6 Fed. L. Rev. 340; Mullan, supra, note 54.

93The principal works are Dicey, Introduction to the Study of the Law of the Constitution (1885), and The Development of Administrative Law in England (1915) 31 L.Q.R. 148.

94 See Symposium on Judicial Administration (1975) 3 Hofstra L. Rev. 647.

compatible with private-law presuppositions state power? 5 Most of the abuses of adjudication are technical, dilatory and not directed to the merits of a dispute. In addition, adjudica- tion assumes an umpiral view of the decision-maker which restricts his role to a more passive supervision of the review process. Finally, the zero-sum orientation of adversarial adjudication fosters pro- cedural wrangling. By contrast, a review process which suppresses and penalizes mutual harassment and which rests on the consent of participants cannot enhance the ascendancy of the state. Ex- perience elsewhere seems to suggest that a mediational procedure may actually limit the power of the administration to argue pro- cedural mattersf 6 Consequently, pragmatic objections to a me- diational procedure for implied due process review also do not seem justified.

A fourth criticism of the proposal arises because supervision on formal or ultra vires grounds remains vested in the courts. The objection is simply that creation of a competing review jurisdiction will not prevent concerns similar to those which led to this proposal from manifesting themselves in ordinary judicial review applica- tions. It is true that the formalistic exercise of classifying func- tions will continue to prevail in review proceedings before the courts; but this is simply to recognize that the problems heretofore resolved by reference to classification (availability of certiorari, right to reconsider, sub-delegation, immunity from tort liability and so forth) will continue to exist. If the negative features of classification can be avoided in one aspect of review proceedings by adoption of a new model, the fact that characterization apparent- ly remains necessary in others should not preclude amendment.

A further aspect of the argument that a procedural review panel should not be established is that it creates a conflict of review jurisdictions, namely, between ordinary judicial review and pro- cedural review. Apart from the general point that multiple juris- dictions are always difficult to manage in practice, 91 it may be suggested that problems of primary jurisdiction, exhaustion and conflicting determinations will be insuperable. Yet a rule such as “formal jurisdictional questions resulting from the interpretation of enabling statutes” could well be established as the criterion of differentiation. Currently, the Bar has little trouble deciding when the issue to be argued is one of natural justice rather than pro-

9fiFor an argument that the law of standing has had precisely this effect

see Vining, supra, note 17, passim.

98See generally Brown & Garner, supra, note 56. 97See Evans’s unpublished comment on a paper by Mullan at a con-

ference held at Osgoode Hall Law School on 18 February 1977.

cedural ultra vires; there is no reason to suspect that creation of a new panel will suddenly deprive it of this insight.98

A final criticism is that there are simply not enough competent individuals to staff the review tribunal. This point may be quickly dispatched: even in the most pessimistic hypothesis, the panel need have no more than twenty members. Of these one would expect about half to be selected because of expertise in adjudica- tion, with perhaps one or two members representing other deci- sional paradigms. Finding and recruiting such a small number of tribunal members should not be a difficult task, as the Bar itself provides a large pool of candidates for many of the required spe- cialities. Of course, it is necessary to train the panel for its task, to provide usual guarantees of independence, to offer adequate remuneration, to organize an efficient secretariat and to develop internal procedures and policies. Yet these are technical matters in analogous contexts. 9 which have not proved unmanageable Consequently, of the pragmatic objections which may be raised against implementing this model, only one, the readjustment of the profession to non-judicial and non-adjudicative procedural review, is significant. Yet, for the reasons given above, any resistance to the model may be overcome, and a genuine commitment to the new panel generated.

Briefly, both constitutional and pragmatic objections to the model proposed can, for the most part, be answered. Section 96 problems are capable of being surmounted at the provincial level, and they do not arise in the federal sphere; the efficacy of privative clauses is a minor issue. Pragmatic criticisms concerning efficiency, staffing, attitude, jurisdictional conflict and the attitude of the Bar are also not conclusive. Hence, while the model’s assumptions may be challenged, other objections to a procedural review tribunal are not insurmountable.

C. Conclusion

The model suggested for institutionalizing procedural review of administrative decisions ultimately rests on beliefs about the nature

98 Nevertheless, the continuing problem of defining the jurisdiction of the Ontario Divisional Court is evidence of the difficulty of partial reform. See Evans, Judicial Review in Ontario – Some Problems of Pouring Old Wine into New Bottles (1977) 55 Can. Bar Rev. 148.

99 See, e.g., Issalys, The Professions Tribunal and the Control of Ethical

Conduct among Professionals (1978) 24 McGill L.J 588.

of implied procedural fairness and the function of supervision on that basis. The establishment of a process of conciliation, by per- sons expert in the forms of various mechanisms for ordering human affairs, undertaken within decisional paradigms chosen by the parties, and directed to developing and implementing better ad- ministrative procedures, as well as fostering a role morality con- sistent with these procedures, is the guiding purpose of this model. Although it envisions non-judicial review and non-adjudicative pro- cedures, and although it is directed to more than the conclusive resolution of procedural complaints in individual cases, it never- theless falls broadly within the common law tradition. The proposal capitalizes on the theoretical revolution in implied procedural review resulting from the fairness doctrine, without judicializing bureaucratic procedures or compromising the effectiveness of the administrative process.

III. Procedural fairness in perspective

Too often the field of administrative law has been characterized by disputes which produce much heat but little light. In the literature of judicial review, positions have been caricatured in the past as pro-court or pro-agency and attitudes which sustain them similarly qualified. Recent writings, however, seem to be more oriented to exploring theoretical foundations of administrative law.100 Moreover, since courts are now assuming a more activist posture, writers are devoting greater attention to the constitutional and political implications of judicial review. Even Law Reform Commissions and other agencies are beginning to address the fundamental issues and assumptions which shape our political ideology and governmental institutions.’0′ As the perennial problems of administrative law receive more sophisticated analysis, the “less illuminating disputes of the thirties’ ‘ 0 2 are becoming less frequent.

10oSee, e.g., Wright, The Courts and the Rule-making Process (1974) 59 Cornell L. Rev. 375; Chayes, supra, note 57; Arthurs, supra, note 4; Stewart, The Reformation of American Administrative Law (1975) 88 Harv. L. Rev. 1667; Rabin, Administrative Law in Transition: A Discipline in Search of an Organizing Principle (1977) 72 Nw. U. L. Rev. 120; Scalia, The AL Fiasco – A Reprise (1979) 47 U. Chi. L. Rev. 57; Ginsburg, Panel IV: Improving the Administrative Process – Time for a New A.P.A. (1980) 32 Admin. L. Rev. 285;Vining, supra, note 17; Davis, Discretionary Justice (1969).

101 See, e.g., Law Reform Commission of Canada, Independent Administra- tive Agencies (1980); Economic Council of Canada, Responsible Regulation (1979).

102 Willis, supra, note 26, 360.

The adoption of the doctrine of procedural fairness by the Supreme Court of Canada in the Nicholson case illustrates the contribution thoughtful scholarship can make to administrative law. It has already produced one careful analysis of several aspects of the theory of judicial review. 10 3 Yet, assuming the judiciary’s con- tinued interest in extensive implied supervision, and given the prac- this interest has produced, legal writers must tical difficulties attempt to reconcile divergent jurisprudential themes, even when traditional reconciliation notions of procedural review. 04

involves substantial readjustment of

In law, developments which often first appear as small glosses on received doctrine eventually transform vast areas of learning. The theory of fairness is one such development. It makes explicit many recent, but implicit, challenges to shibboleths of the common law. Adjudication is no longer the optimal paradigm of due process in legal decision-making. Adversariness no longer has a claim to superiority as a means of resolving disputes. Legal rules themselves cannot pretend to absolve individuals of personal responsibility for juridical solutions. The reproach and censure associated with for judicial decrees are revealed as second-best mechanisms ensuring respect for procedural propriety. The theory of fairness embarks administrative law, and eventually all law, on a path which ends with the recognition that law is not merely a collection of signs, words and concepts having only discursive meaning. It is also symbol, a metaphor of human society.0 5

One might now say, with some degree of certainty, that the in- tellectual challenge of administrative law in the eighties is not to ignore the institutional difficulties created by the growing bureau-

10.3 Loughlin, supra, note 2. -104E.g., Fiss, The Forms of Justice (1979) 93 Harv. L. Rev. 1; Katzmann, Judicial Intervention and Organization Theory: Changing Bureaucratic Behavior and Policy (1980) 89 Yale L.J. 513; and Tushnet, Truth, Justice and the American Way: An Interpretation of Public Law Scholarship in the Seventies (1979) 57 Tex. L. Rev. 1307.

105 1 am, of course, drawing heavily on Langer, Philosophy in a New Key, 3d ed. (1957), in these concluding remarks. See also Vining, supra, note 17, 181:

Law is symbol as well as system…. A symbol does not merely describe a thought. It is not a cipher, cool and detached. … Law and litigation have served to separate individuals from one another, to push and keep them apart. … Law need no longer symbolize what it has in the past. However potent a symbol is, it can change. … Litigation can now bring home as forcefully as any religious ritual that each of us is in fact involved in mankind. Public law has come of age.

cratic state and the tentative attempts by courts to respond to this growth; rather, it is to develop and staff institutions to resolve them. Accordingly, the highest calling for administrative lawyers will be not to destroy the symbolism of the law but to transform it, in the search for new meaning in the problems of public law.100

106 1 am grateful to the participants at the Canadian Conference on the History and Philosophy of Law, held at the University of Windsor, June 9, 10 and 11, 1980, for their insistence upon the philosophical importance of the emerging theory of procedural fairness. See the forthcoming proceedings of the Conference for a paper which develops this theme.

Thank you to our sponsors

essay on procedural fairness

Barter McKellar

Procedural Fairness in South African Regulatory Decisions: Transparency and Fairness

essay on procedural fairness

Ensuring Procedural Fairness in South Africa's Regulatory Bodies

In South Africa, the concept of procedural fairness is a cornerstone of administrative law, particularly in the actions and decisions of regulatory bodies. This article provides an in-depth understanding of procedural fairness, focusing on the requirements for transparency, opportunities to be heard and the right to fair administrative action.

What is Procedural Fairness?

Procedural fairness, also known as natural justice, refers to the procedures used by regulatory bodies to ensure decisions are made fairly, impartially and reasonably. It's a fundamental aspect of the administrative process in South Africa, ensuring that the rights of individuals and organizations are protected.

Transparency in Decision-Making

Openness and Clarity : Transparency is key in the operations of regulatory bodies. It involves clear, open communication about how decisions are made and the criteria used in these processes.

Accessible Information : Ensuring that relevant information is easily accessible to those affected by decisions is a critical component of procedural fairness.

The Right to be Heard

Opportunity to Present Cases : Individuals and organizations have the right to present their case before a decision is made. This includes access to a fair hearing where they can state their views and provide evidence.

Responding to Evidence : Affected parties should be given a chance to respond to any evidence or arguments presented against them.

Fair Administrative Action

Impartial Decision Making : Decisions must be made impartially, without bias and based on relevant factors only.

Reasoned Decisions : Regulatory bodies are expected to provide reasons for their decisions, allowing for transparency and accountability.

The Legal Framework for Procedural Fairness in South Africa

South Africa's legal framework, including the Constitution and the Promotion of Administrative Justice Act (PAJA), provides the basis for procedural fairness. These laws outline the standards and requirements that regulatory bodies must adhere to.

Challenges and Remedies

Addressing Challenges : Despite clear legal standards, challenges in procedural fairness do arise. These may include lack of transparency, insufficient opportunities to be heard or biased decision-making.

Legal Remedies : Affected parties have legal remedies available, such as appeals or judicial reviews, to challenge decisions that do not comply with the standards of procedural fairness.

Conclusion: The Significance of Procedural Fairness

Procedural fairness is essential for maintaining trust in South Africa's regulatory system. It ensures decisions are made justly, respecting the rights and interests of all parties involved.

essay on procedural fairness

Ensuring Accountability and Oversight of Regulatory Bodies in South Africa

Navigating the extent of powers of regulatory bodies in south africa.

ipl-logo

Procedural Fairness

When it is talked about procedural fairness what is meant is equal treatment by the law and the administration, this applies to both people and corporations. When an issue arises with respect to that principle, one of the pillars of administrative law is usually the solution and that is judicial review. Those are the two aspects of this paper which will be narrated by the question of “why would the French system not be an alternative to the UK?” this question is an essential for the administrative law because it will present the differences and efficacy of current practices, which highlights shortcomings and points requiring amendments. This affects both the professionals in the field and the society, because it has influence over the efficacy …show more content…

Firstly, unlike many other states the UK does not have a written constitution as such but rather refers to existing statutes and precedents as such, according to which the ultimate source of law is the Parliament, which means that in the course of a term many statutes and precedents can be amended or eliminated with or without replacing them. Secondly, the constitution establishes the powers of the state, according to which all issues regarding the law shall be addressed to the courts of the UK, which essentially boils down to the fact that administrative cases are heard by the same courts . Whether or not a highly centralized court system is a benefit will be discussed further below. For this section however, it is needed to present what are the established requirements for a review according to the law some of which are if the law, policy, or a decision is has made an error in determining the facts of the issue or if the wrong law was applied, another precedent not providing a fair hearing, and proportionality established in result of EU legislation, if the decision was made by the wrong institution of government and various others prerequisites that are dependent on …show more content…

Firstly, there is an independent assigned institution that concerns itself with issues regarding administrative procedures, it is called the Council of State it still consists of legal professionals that have proven their level of dedication and have gotten an education that differs from university and have passed a specific examination. Furthermore, they also have an advisory function when policies are made, which is to say that a constitutional check has been through policies before they are implemented . Proportionality and equality are the main principles of the review in Council d’état. The role of the Council has changed through time especially since the establishment of administrative courts who hear cases and have power to award remedies, while the Council might advise the courts on how to decide the case, that would happen when a claim against a policy or a decision is addressed to it and on its turn the Council asks for clarification the respective governmental agency, with that function it can help amend policies and assist administrative courts at the same

Similarities Between Texas And Federal Court System

Moreover, this hierarchical arrangement ensures that cases are heard and decisions made at various levels of the judiciary, allowing for appeals and upholding the principle of checks and balances, guaranteeing impartiality and fairness.

What Are The Greatest Challenges Within The Judicial Branch Of Government

The judicial branch has paved its way to gain resilience amongst the three branches. It has gain more power over the years, and usually has the final “say so,” in parliament

Judicial Branch Research Paper

Judicial review is a term that refers to a court's review of a decision of a lower court in order to determine whether an error was made. The court has power to pass judgement on the constitutionality of actions of state and federal legislatures and courts. The judicial review has three parts first it allows justice to be served by striking down erroneous decisions by lower counts, second appellate lower courts, third important controversies regarding the law are examined and resolved for the future audience of courts and individuals. Judicial review is a key part of the coexistence of the three

Justice Brennan Racial Fairness

Although Justice Brennan’s time on the Supreme Court came to an end in 1990 due to old age and ill health, his influence continues to be felt today, both in the courtroom and outside of it. Indeed, the length of the jurist’s service to the American people effective guaranteed that this would be the case. Despite this obituary primarily focussing on his decisive opinions concerning racial fairness, Brennan was a vocal and persuasive member of the court in many other instances. For example, in Baker v. Carr (1962), he convinced his peers to uphold the doctrine of “one man, one vote” by mandating redistricting on the basis of population rather than geographic area.

Bias In The Court System

Court System Controversy Although there is a standard for courtrooms and how they should function it is, nevertheless, unrealistic and unable to be upheld due to bias, prejudice- either conscious or subconscious, and stereotyping. Initially, bias is using personal experiences to hold strong emotions toward a variety of groups of people. Bias can affect the court system in countless ways.

Jury Racial Injustice

Jury Systems and Racial Injustice Juries are the way we make sure trials are fair, but when your jury is biased the result of the trial are often inequitable. Today we do our best to make sure trials have impartial jurors, but this was not always the case. In the 1930’s, and a lot of other decades too, the right for African Americans to have an unbiased jury was not fulfilled. This caused many African Americans to be sentenced to death when they otherwise would not have been.

Judicial Branch In Canada

Judicial review allows for the challenging of state actions in order to ensure that decisions made by the government follow laws. In Canada, laws must be brought to the supreme court to be challenged and the court may not arbitrarily open cases. The goal of judicial review is to assure citizens that power is not being abused at any level of government and that the rule of law is being followed. The Supreme Court of Canada falls under the judicial branch of the government, its role is to interpret the Canadian constitution and decide whether or not laws are constitutional.

The Constrained Court

The Court’s effectiveness relies on the institutional capacities as well as the ruling’s popularity. When lower-court judges comply with Supreme Court decisions, rulings can have a substantial effect on social policies, as in the case

Distributive Justice In Health Care

Ethical Complexity of Distribute Justice and Rationing Medicine is a practice based on moral standards applied to clinical values and judgments, also known as medical ethics. Ethical values consists of beneficence, nonmaleficence, autonomy and justice. However, these ethical principles are affected when distributive justice and rationing of health care resources are implemented “…in a world in which need is boundless but resources are not…” (Scheunemann & White, 2011, p. 1630). The historic Hippocratic Oath described the four main principles of medical practice and established a moral conduct for clinicians. Beneficence demands that health care providers develop and maintain skills and knowledge, consider individual circumstances of all patients, and strive for the patient’s benefit.

Essay On Procedural Justice

Definition and Description of Procedural Justice Procedural justice is the act involved in decision making. It incorporates the process of involving transparency and fairness in making decisions. The incorporation of justice in this process is equally essential it entails that all parties allowed to give their views before decision are made concerning a given matter. Some theories state that restorative and distributive justice might not be met but for as long as there is a fair and justice procedure, there is always the possibility of having outcomes that are equitable (Jason &Tyler, 2003).

Equity And Rule Of Law: Is Equity More Determinate

The aim of this article is to critically consider this proposition from a number of different perspectives. It will first describe the historical evolution of Equity and its connection with the Common Law. Then, it will go through to analyse why this proposition is partially correct by talking about how Equity is now more structured due to the presence of equitable maxims. This argument will be supported using a specific maxim that led to clearer equitable rules. Relevant case law will also be used for illustrating how this maxim is being used by the

U. K. History: The Constitutional Reform Act Of 2005

Another thing that worth to explore from U.K history is the Constitutional Reform Act 2005. By Part 3 of the Constitutional Reform Act 2005, the supreme court was established and started work on 1 October 2009.[14]Its assumption is the Lords of Appeal in Ordinary had operated the House of Lords’s judicial functions. 12 judges who appointed as members of the House of Lords, carry out its judicial duties. The Judicial Committee of the Privy Council had exercised the jurisdiction over devolution matters previously. As the new President of the Court, Lord Phillips, has claimed that the previous system had confused people and that with the Supreme Court there would be a clear separation of powers among the judiciary for the first time, the legislature

Case Study: Disparate Treatment Violations

1. Although the Chinese woman doesn 't speak proper English which is crucial to her job performance. The company has no right to terminate her all because she doesn 't speak good English. If I didn 't take this course, I would have honestly believed she should be fired because she can 't speak proper English. However, after reading through the PowerPoints this establishment violated this woman 's right.

Advantages And Disadvantages Of The Common Law System

[5] Common law works in a different way, the judges rather than the Parliament make common law or ‘judge-made law’. Considering criminal and civil cases, the judges take decisions based on the stare decisis principle (Latin “to stand by things decided”, the legal principle of determining points in litigation according to precedent [4]), deliver rulings and create precedents, thus applying the law to real life situations. Therefore, the value of the precedent is very high in the English Common Law system. The strengths of common law

Strengths And Weaknesses Of The Civil Justice System

It was revealed by a survey carried out by National Consumer Council how unhappy and unsatisfactory people were with the Civil Justice System. The main weaknesses identified were that the system being too slow, too complicated for ordinary people to understand and too outdated and costly. In the continued criticism of the system Lord Woolf was appointed by the government who came up with suggestions and solutions to overcome these problems. As a result Civil Procedure Rules came into force on 26th April 1999 introducing different reforms to the system. The rationale of the reforms was to avoid litigation and promote settlement between the parties at dispute.

More about Procedural Fairness

Related topics.

  • Political philosophy
  • Search Menu
  • Browse content in Arts and Humanities
  • Browse content in Archaeology
  • Anglo-Saxon and Medieval Archaeology
  • Archaeological Methodology and Techniques
  • Archaeology by Region
  • Archaeology of Religion
  • Archaeology of Trade and Exchange
  • Biblical Archaeology
  • Contemporary and Public Archaeology
  • Environmental Archaeology
  • Historical Archaeology
  • History and Theory of Archaeology
  • Industrial Archaeology
  • Landscape Archaeology
  • Mortuary Archaeology
  • Prehistoric Archaeology
  • Underwater Archaeology
  • Urban Archaeology
  • Zooarchaeology
  • Browse content in Architecture
  • Architectural Structure and Design
  • History of Architecture
  • Residential and Domestic Buildings
  • Theory of Architecture
  • Browse content in Art
  • Art Subjects and Themes
  • History of Art
  • Industrial and Commercial Art
  • Theory of Art
  • Biographical Studies
  • Byzantine Studies
  • Browse content in Classical Studies
  • Classical History
  • Classical Philosophy
  • Classical Mythology
  • Classical Literature
  • Classical Reception
  • Classical Art and Architecture
  • Classical Oratory and Rhetoric
  • Greek and Roman Epigraphy
  • Greek and Roman Law
  • Greek and Roman Archaeology
  • Greek and Roman Papyrology
  • Late Antiquity
  • Religion in the Ancient World
  • Digital Humanities
  • Browse content in History
  • Colonialism and Imperialism
  • Diplomatic History
  • Environmental History
  • Genealogy, Heraldry, Names, and Honours
  • Genocide and Ethnic Cleansing
  • Historical Geography
  • History by Period
  • History of Agriculture
  • History of Education
  • History of Emotions
  • History of Gender and Sexuality
  • Industrial History
  • Intellectual History
  • International History
  • Labour History
  • Legal and Constitutional History
  • Local and Family History
  • Maritime History
  • Military History
  • National Liberation and Post-Colonialism
  • Oral History
  • Political History
  • Public History
  • Regional and National History
  • Revolutions and Rebellions
  • Slavery and Abolition of Slavery
  • Social and Cultural History
  • Theory, Methods, and Historiography
  • Urban History
  • World History
  • Browse content in Language Teaching and Learning
  • Language Learning (Specific Skills)
  • Language Teaching Theory and Methods
  • Browse content in Linguistics
  • Applied Linguistics
  • Cognitive Linguistics
  • Computational Linguistics
  • Forensic Linguistics
  • Grammar, Syntax and Morphology
  • Historical and Diachronic Linguistics
  • History of English
  • Language Acquisition
  • Language Variation
  • Language Families
  • Language Evolution
  • Language Reference
  • Lexicography
  • Linguistic Theories
  • Linguistic Typology
  • Linguistic Anthropology
  • Phonetics and Phonology
  • Psycholinguistics
  • Sociolinguistics
  • Translation and Interpretation
  • Writing Systems
  • Browse content in Literature
  • Bibliography
  • Children's Literature Studies
  • Literary Studies (Asian)
  • Literary Studies (European)
  • Literary Studies (Eco-criticism)
  • Literary Studies (Modernism)
  • Literary Studies (Romanticism)
  • Literary Studies (American)
  • Literary Studies - World
  • Literary Studies (1500 to 1800)
  • Literary Studies (19th Century)
  • Literary Studies (20th Century onwards)
  • Literary Studies (African American Literature)
  • Literary Studies (British and Irish)
  • Literary Studies (Early and Medieval)
  • Literary Studies (Fiction, Novelists, and Prose Writers)
  • Literary Studies (Gender Studies)
  • Literary Studies (Graphic Novels)
  • Literary Studies (History of the Book)
  • Literary Studies (Plays and Playwrights)
  • Literary Studies (Poetry and Poets)
  • Literary Studies (Postcolonial Literature)
  • Literary Studies (Queer Studies)
  • Literary Studies (Science Fiction)
  • Literary Studies (Travel Literature)
  • Literary Studies (War Literature)
  • Literary Studies (Women's Writing)
  • Literary Theory and Cultural Studies
  • Mythology and Folklore
  • Shakespeare Studies and Criticism
  • Browse content in Media Studies
  • Browse content in Music
  • Applied Music
  • Dance and Music
  • Ethics in Music
  • Ethnomusicology
  • Gender and Sexuality in Music
  • Medicine and Music
  • Music Cultures
  • Music and Religion
  • Music and Culture
  • Music and Media
  • Music Education and Pedagogy
  • Music Theory and Analysis
  • Musical Scores, Lyrics, and Libretti
  • Musical Structures, Styles, and Techniques
  • Musicology and Music History
  • Performance Practice and Studies
  • Race and Ethnicity in Music
  • Sound Studies
  • Browse content in Performing Arts
  • Browse content in Philosophy
  • Aesthetics and Philosophy of Art
  • Epistemology
  • Feminist Philosophy
  • History of Western Philosophy
  • Metaphysics
  • Moral Philosophy
  • Non-Western Philosophy
  • Philosophy of Science
  • Philosophy of Action
  • Philosophy of Law
  • Philosophy of Religion
  • Philosophy of Language
  • Philosophy of Mind
  • Philosophy of Perception
  • Philosophy of Mathematics and Logic
  • Practical Ethics
  • Social and Political Philosophy
  • Browse content in Religion
  • Biblical Studies
  • Christianity
  • East Asian Religions
  • History of Religion
  • Judaism and Jewish Studies
  • Qumran Studies
  • Religion and Education
  • Religion and Health
  • Religion and Politics
  • Religion and Science
  • Religion and Law
  • Religion and Art, Literature, and Music
  • Religious Studies
  • Browse content in Society and Culture
  • Cookery, Food, and Drink
  • Cultural Studies
  • Customs and Traditions
  • Ethical Issues and Debates
  • Hobbies, Games, Arts and Crafts
  • Lifestyle, Home, and Garden
  • Natural world, Country Life, and Pets
  • Popular Beliefs and Controversial Knowledge
  • Sports and Outdoor Recreation
  • Technology and Society
  • Travel and Holiday
  • Visual Culture
  • Browse content in Law
  • Arbitration
  • Browse content in Company and Commercial Law
  • Commercial Law
  • Company Law
  • Browse content in Comparative Law
  • Systems of Law
  • Competition Law
  • Browse content in Constitutional and Administrative Law
  • Government Powers
  • Judicial Review
  • Local Government Law
  • Military and Defence Law
  • Parliamentary and Legislative Practice
  • Construction Law
  • Contract Law
  • Browse content in Criminal Law
  • Criminal Procedure
  • Criminal Evidence Law
  • Sentencing and Punishment
  • Employment and Labour Law
  • Environment and Energy Law
  • Browse content in Financial Law
  • Banking Law
  • Insolvency Law
  • History of Law
  • Human Rights and Immigration
  • Intellectual Property Law
  • Browse content in International Law
  • Private International Law and Conflict of Laws
  • Public International Law
  • IT and Communications Law
  • Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law
  • Law and Politics
  • Law and Society
  • Browse content in Legal System and Practice
  • Courts and Procedure
  • Legal Skills and Practice
  • Primary Sources of Law
  • Regulation of Legal Profession
  • Medical and Healthcare Law
  • Browse content in Policing
  • Criminal Investigation and Detection
  • Police and Security Services
  • Police Procedure and Law
  • Police Regional Planning
  • Browse content in Property Law
  • Personal Property Law
  • Study and Revision
  • Terrorism and National Security Law
  • Browse content in Trusts Law
  • Wills and Probate or Succession
  • Browse content in Medicine and Health
  • Browse content in Allied Health Professions
  • Arts Therapies
  • Clinical Science
  • Dietetics and Nutrition
  • Occupational Therapy
  • Operating Department Practice
  • Physiotherapy
  • Radiography
  • Speech and Language Therapy
  • Browse content in Anaesthetics
  • General Anaesthesia
  • Neuroanaesthesia
  • Browse content in Clinical Medicine
  • Acute Medicine
  • Cardiovascular Medicine
  • Clinical Genetics
  • Clinical Pharmacology and Therapeutics
  • Dermatology
  • Endocrinology and Diabetes
  • Gastroenterology
  • Genito-urinary Medicine
  • Geriatric Medicine
  • Infectious Diseases
  • Medical Oncology
  • Medical Toxicology
  • Pain Medicine
  • Palliative Medicine
  • Rehabilitation Medicine
  • Respiratory Medicine and Pulmonology
  • Rheumatology
  • Sleep Medicine
  • Sports and Exercise Medicine
  • Clinical Neuroscience
  • Community Medical Services
  • Critical Care
  • Emergency Medicine
  • Forensic Medicine
  • Haematology
  • History of Medicine
  • Browse content in Medical Dentistry
  • Oral and Maxillofacial Surgery
  • Paediatric Dentistry
  • Restorative Dentistry and Orthodontics
  • Surgical Dentistry
  • Medical Ethics
  • Browse content in Medical Skills
  • Clinical Skills
  • Communication Skills
  • Nursing Skills
  • Surgical Skills
  • Medical Statistics and Methodology
  • Browse content in Neurology
  • Clinical Neurophysiology
  • Neuropathology
  • Nursing Studies
  • Browse content in Obstetrics and Gynaecology
  • Gynaecology
  • Occupational Medicine
  • Ophthalmology
  • Otolaryngology (ENT)
  • Browse content in Paediatrics
  • Neonatology
  • Browse content in Pathology
  • Chemical Pathology
  • Clinical Cytogenetics and Molecular Genetics
  • Histopathology
  • Medical Microbiology and Virology
  • Patient Education and Information
  • Browse content in Pharmacology
  • Psychopharmacology
  • Browse content in Popular Health
  • Caring for Others
  • Complementary and Alternative Medicine
  • Self-help and Personal Development
  • Browse content in Preclinical Medicine
  • Cell Biology
  • Molecular Biology and Genetics
  • Reproduction, Growth and Development
  • Primary Care
  • Professional Development in Medicine
  • Browse content in Psychiatry
  • Addiction Medicine
  • Child and Adolescent Psychiatry
  • Forensic Psychiatry
  • Learning Disabilities
  • Old Age Psychiatry
  • Psychotherapy
  • Browse content in Public Health and Epidemiology
  • Epidemiology
  • Public Health
  • Browse content in Radiology
  • Clinical Radiology
  • Interventional Radiology
  • Nuclear Medicine
  • Radiation Oncology
  • Reproductive Medicine
  • Browse content in Surgery
  • Cardiothoracic Surgery
  • Gastro-intestinal and Colorectal Surgery
  • General Surgery
  • Neurosurgery
  • Paediatric Surgery
  • Peri-operative Care
  • Plastic and Reconstructive Surgery
  • Surgical Oncology
  • Transplant Surgery
  • Trauma and Orthopaedic Surgery
  • Vascular Surgery
  • Browse content in Science and Mathematics
  • Browse content in Biological Sciences
  • Aquatic Biology
  • Biochemistry
  • Bioinformatics and Computational Biology
  • Developmental Biology
  • Ecology and Conservation
  • Evolutionary Biology
  • Genetics and Genomics
  • Microbiology
  • Molecular and Cell Biology
  • Natural History
  • Plant Sciences and Forestry
  • Research Methods in Life Sciences
  • Structural Biology
  • Systems Biology
  • Zoology and Animal Sciences
  • Browse content in Chemistry
  • Analytical Chemistry
  • Computational Chemistry
  • Crystallography
  • Environmental Chemistry
  • Industrial Chemistry
  • Inorganic Chemistry
  • Materials Chemistry
  • Medicinal Chemistry
  • Mineralogy and Gems
  • Organic Chemistry
  • Physical Chemistry
  • Polymer Chemistry
  • Study and Communication Skills in Chemistry
  • Theoretical Chemistry
  • Browse content in Computer Science
  • Artificial Intelligence
  • Computer Architecture and Logic Design
  • Game Studies
  • Human-Computer Interaction
  • Mathematical Theory of Computation
  • Programming Languages
  • Software Engineering
  • Systems Analysis and Design
  • Virtual Reality
  • Browse content in Computing
  • Business Applications
  • Computer Security
  • Computer Games
  • Computer Networking and Communications
  • Digital Lifestyle
  • Graphical and Digital Media Applications
  • Operating Systems
  • Browse content in Earth Sciences and Geography
  • Atmospheric Sciences
  • Environmental Geography
  • Geology and the Lithosphere
  • Maps and Map-making
  • Meteorology and Climatology
  • Oceanography and Hydrology
  • Palaeontology
  • Physical Geography and Topography
  • Regional Geography
  • Soil Science
  • Urban Geography
  • Browse content in Engineering and Technology
  • Agriculture and Farming
  • Biological Engineering
  • Civil Engineering, Surveying, and Building
  • Electronics and Communications Engineering
  • Energy Technology
  • Engineering (General)
  • Environmental Science, Engineering, and Technology
  • History of Engineering and Technology
  • Mechanical Engineering and Materials
  • Technology of Industrial Chemistry
  • Transport Technology and Trades
  • Browse content in Environmental Science
  • Applied Ecology (Environmental Science)
  • Conservation of the Environment (Environmental Science)
  • Environmental Sustainability
  • Environmentalist Thought and Ideology (Environmental Science)
  • Management of Land and Natural Resources (Environmental Science)
  • Natural Disasters (Environmental Science)
  • Nuclear Issues (Environmental Science)
  • Pollution and Threats to the Environment (Environmental Science)
  • Social Impact of Environmental Issues (Environmental Science)
  • History of Science and Technology
  • Browse content in Materials Science
  • Ceramics and Glasses
  • Composite Materials
  • Metals, Alloying, and Corrosion
  • Nanotechnology
  • Browse content in Mathematics
  • Applied Mathematics
  • Biomathematics and Statistics
  • History of Mathematics
  • Mathematical Education
  • Mathematical Finance
  • Mathematical Analysis
  • Numerical and Computational Mathematics
  • Probability and Statistics
  • Pure Mathematics
  • Browse content in Neuroscience
  • Cognition and Behavioural Neuroscience
  • Development of the Nervous System
  • Disorders of the Nervous System
  • History of Neuroscience
  • Invertebrate Neurobiology
  • Molecular and Cellular Systems
  • Neuroendocrinology and Autonomic Nervous System
  • Neuroscientific Techniques
  • Sensory and Motor Systems
  • Browse content in Physics
  • Astronomy and Astrophysics
  • Atomic, Molecular, and Optical Physics
  • Biological and Medical Physics
  • Classical Mechanics
  • Computational Physics
  • Condensed Matter Physics
  • Electromagnetism, Optics, and Acoustics
  • History of Physics
  • Mathematical and Statistical Physics
  • Measurement Science
  • Nuclear Physics
  • Particles and Fields
  • Plasma Physics
  • Quantum Physics
  • Relativity and Gravitation
  • Semiconductor and Mesoscopic Physics
  • Browse content in Psychology
  • Affective Sciences
  • Clinical Psychology
  • Cognitive Neuroscience
  • Cognitive Psychology
  • Criminal and Forensic Psychology
  • Developmental Psychology
  • Educational Psychology
  • Evolutionary Psychology
  • Health Psychology
  • History and Systems in Psychology
  • Music Psychology
  • Neuropsychology
  • Organizational Psychology
  • Psychological Assessment and Testing
  • Psychology of Human-Technology Interaction
  • Psychology Professional Development and Training
  • Research Methods in Psychology
  • Social Psychology
  • Browse content in Social Sciences
  • Browse content in Anthropology
  • Anthropology of Religion
  • Human Evolution
  • Medical Anthropology
  • Physical Anthropology
  • Regional Anthropology
  • Social and Cultural Anthropology
  • Theory and Practice of Anthropology
  • Browse content in Business and Management
  • Business Strategy
  • Business History
  • Business Ethics
  • Business and Government
  • Business and Technology
  • Business and the Environment
  • Comparative Management
  • Corporate Governance
  • Corporate Social Responsibility
  • Entrepreneurship
  • Health Management
  • Human Resource Management
  • Industrial and Employment Relations
  • Industry Studies
  • Information and Communication Technologies
  • International Business
  • Knowledge Management
  • Management and Management Techniques
  • Operations Management
  • Organizational Theory and Behaviour
  • Pensions and Pension Management
  • Public and Nonprofit Management
  • Strategic Management
  • Supply Chain Management
  • Browse content in Criminology and Criminal Justice
  • Criminal Justice
  • Criminology
  • Forms of Crime
  • International and Comparative Criminology
  • Youth Violence and Juvenile Justice
  • Development Studies
  • Browse content in Economics
  • Agricultural, Environmental, and Natural Resource Economics
  • Asian Economics
  • Behavioural Finance
  • Behavioural Economics and Neuroeconomics
  • Econometrics and Mathematical Economics
  • Economic Systems
  • Economic Methodology
  • Economic History
  • Economic Development and Growth
  • Financial Markets
  • Financial Institutions and Services
  • General Economics and Teaching
  • Health, Education, and Welfare
  • History of Economic Thought
  • International Economics
  • Labour and Demographic Economics
  • Law and Economics
  • Macroeconomics and Monetary Economics
  • Microeconomics
  • Public Economics
  • Urban, Rural, and Regional Economics
  • Welfare Economics
  • Browse content in Education
  • Adult Education and Continuous Learning
  • Care and Counselling of Students
  • Early Childhood and Elementary Education
  • Educational Equipment and Technology
  • Educational Strategies and Policy
  • Higher and Further Education
  • Organization and Management of Education
  • Philosophy and Theory of Education
  • Schools Studies
  • Secondary Education
  • Teaching of a Specific Subject
  • Teaching of Specific Groups and Special Educational Needs
  • Teaching Skills and Techniques
  • Browse content in Environment
  • Applied Ecology (Social Science)
  • Climate Change
  • Conservation of the Environment (Social Science)
  • Environmentalist Thought and Ideology (Social Science)
  • Natural Disasters (Environment)
  • Social Impact of Environmental Issues (Social Science)
  • Browse content in Human Geography
  • Cultural Geography
  • Economic Geography
  • Political Geography
  • Browse content in Interdisciplinary Studies
  • Communication Studies
  • Museums, Libraries, and Information Sciences
  • Browse content in Politics
  • African Politics
  • Asian Politics
  • Chinese Politics
  • Comparative Politics
  • Conflict Politics
  • Elections and Electoral Studies
  • Environmental Politics
  • European Union
  • Foreign Policy
  • Gender and Politics
  • Human Rights and Politics
  • Indian Politics
  • International Relations
  • International Organization (Politics)
  • International Political Economy
  • Irish Politics
  • Latin American Politics
  • Middle Eastern Politics
  • Political Methodology
  • Political Communication
  • Political Philosophy
  • Political Sociology
  • Political Theory
  • Political Behaviour
  • Political Economy
  • Political Institutions
  • Politics and Law
  • Public Administration
  • Public Policy
  • Quantitative Political Methodology
  • Regional Political Studies
  • Russian Politics
  • Security Studies
  • State and Local Government
  • UK Politics
  • US Politics
  • Browse content in Regional and Area Studies
  • African Studies
  • Asian Studies
  • East Asian Studies
  • Japanese Studies
  • Latin American Studies
  • Middle Eastern Studies
  • Native American Studies
  • Scottish Studies
  • Browse content in Research and Information
  • Research Methods
  • Browse content in Social Work
  • Addictions and Substance Misuse
  • Adoption and Fostering
  • Care of the Elderly
  • Child and Adolescent Social Work
  • Couple and Family Social Work
  • Developmental and Physical Disabilities Social Work
  • Direct Practice and Clinical Social Work
  • Emergency Services
  • Human Behaviour and the Social Environment
  • International and Global Issues in Social Work
  • Mental and Behavioural Health
  • Social Justice and Human Rights
  • Social Policy and Advocacy
  • Social Work and Crime and Justice
  • Social Work Macro Practice
  • Social Work Practice Settings
  • Social Work Research and Evidence-based Practice
  • Welfare and Benefit Systems
  • Browse content in Sociology
  • Childhood Studies
  • Community Development
  • Comparative and Historical Sociology
  • Economic Sociology
  • Gender and Sexuality
  • Gerontology and Ageing
  • Health, Illness, and Medicine
  • Marriage and the Family
  • Migration Studies
  • Occupations, Professions, and Work
  • Organizations
  • Population and Demography
  • Race and Ethnicity
  • Social Theory
  • Social Movements and Social Change
  • Social Research and Statistics
  • Social Stratification, Inequality, and Mobility
  • Sociology of Religion
  • Sociology of Education
  • Sport and Leisure
  • Urban and Rural Studies
  • Browse content in Warfare and Defence
  • Defence Strategy, Planning, and Research
  • Land Forces and Warfare
  • Military Administration
  • Military Life and Institutions
  • Naval Forces and Warfare
  • Other Warfare and Defence Issues
  • Peace Studies and Conflict Resolution
  • Weapons and Equipment

Due Process and Fair Procedures: A Study of Administrative Procedures

  • < Previous chapter
  • Next chapter >

11 The Legal Approach to Procedural Fairness

  • Published: January 1997
  • Cite Icon Cite
  • Permissions Icon Permissions

This chapter describes and analyses the general judicial approach to procedural fairness. It examines a number of issues: the tests developed by English law as to who is entitled to fair procedures; the extent to which abstract principles are translated into more detailed procedural rules; and the general judicial approach to exactly what procedural fairness requires and how those requirements are reconciled by the courts with competing considerations, especially costs.

Signed in as

Institutional accounts.

  • Google Scholar Indexing
  • GoogleCrawler [DO NOT DELETE]

Personal account

  • Sign in with email/username & password
  • Get email alerts
  • Save searches
  • Purchase content
  • Activate your purchase/trial code

Institutional access

  • Sign in with a library card Sign in with username/password Recommend to your librarian
  • Institutional account management
  • Get help with access

Access to content on Oxford Academic is often provided through institutional subscriptions and purchases. If you are a member of an institution with an active account, you may be able to access content in one of the following ways:

IP based access

Typically, access is provided across an institutional network to a range of IP addresses. This authentication occurs automatically, and it is not possible to sign out of an IP authenticated account.

Sign in through your institution

Choose this option to get remote access when outside your institution. Shibboleth/Open Athens technology is used to provide single sign-on between your institution’s website and Oxford Academic.

  • Click Sign in through your institution.
  • Select your institution from the list provided, which will take you to your institution's website to sign in.
  • When on the institution site, please use the credentials provided by your institution. Do not use an Oxford Academic personal account.
  • Following successful sign in, you will be returned to Oxford Academic.

If your institution is not listed or you cannot sign in to your institution’s website, please contact your librarian or administrator.

Sign in with a library card

Enter your library card number to sign in. If you cannot sign in, please contact your librarian.

Society Members

Society member access to a journal is achieved in one of the following ways:

Sign in through society site

Many societies offer single sign-on between the society website and Oxford Academic. If you see ‘Sign in through society site’ in the sign in pane within a journal:

  • Click Sign in through society site.
  • When on the society site, please use the credentials provided by that society. Do not use an Oxford Academic personal account.

If you do not have a society account or have forgotten your username or password, please contact your society.

Sign in using a personal account

Some societies use Oxford Academic personal accounts to provide access to their members. See below.

A personal account can be used to get email alerts, save searches, purchase content, and activate subscriptions.

Some societies use Oxford Academic personal accounts to provide access to their members.

Viewing your signed in accounts

Click the account icon in the top right to:

  • View your signed in personal account and access account management features.
  • View the institutional accounts that are providing access.

Signed in but can't access content

Oxford Academic is home to a wide variety of products. The institutional subscription may not cover the content that you are trying to access. If you believe you should have access to that content, please contact your librarian.

For librarians and administrators, your personal account also provides access to institutional account management. Here you will find options to view and activate subscriptions, manage institutional settings and access options, access usage statistics, and more.

Our books are available by subscription or purchase to libraries and institutions.

  • About Oxford Academic
  • Publish journals with us
  • University press partners
  • What we publish
  • New features  
  • Open access
  • Rights and permissions
  • Accessibility
  • Advertising
  • Media enquiries
  • Oxford University Press
  • Oxford Languages
  • University of Oxford

Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University's objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide

  • Copyright © 2024 Oxford University Press
  • Cookie settings
  • Cookie policy
  • Privacy policy
  • Legal notice

This Feature Is Available To Subscribers Only

Sign In or Create an Account

This PDF is available to Subscribers Only

For full access to this pdf, sign in to an existing account, or purchase an annual subscription.

Hamburger menu

  • Free Essays
  • Citation Generator

Preview

Essay On Procedural Fairness

essay on procedural fairness

You May Also Find These Documents Helpful

John rawls fairness approach: a case study.

John Rawls’ Fairness Approach is an appropriate ethical framework to use when assessing this dilemma. This approach questions if everyone involved is being treated fairly (is there favoritism and discrimination?). The Fairness Approach examines how fairly or unfairly the actions of an individual or group distribute benefits and burdens everyone else. With this approach, consistency of treatment among persons is key. The only insistence when treatment must differ is if there is a morally relevant difference between people (Andre, Meyer, Shanks, Velasquez, 1989). There are three different kinds of justice -- Distributive, Restorative, and Compensatory. Distributive justice focuses on the benefits and burdens evenly distributed amongst society’s…

Analysis Of Mike Rezendes Code Of Ethics

Toward the end of the movie, Mark Ruffalo’s character, Mike Rezendes, flips out dramatically about getting this story out to the public to make sure no other kids become victims.(2015) The head editor on the team, Robby Robinson, tells Rezendes to be patient that they aren’t just going after the individuals, they are going after the system. Robinson makes this ethical decision based on that he doesn’t know what will happen in the future, but if they just release the priest's names the same thing will occur over and over. The only way Robinson states will cure this terrible tragedy, is if they bring down the whole system who is in charge. Being a journalist, Robinson uses his ethical code to make sure he can get a reliable source that is an…

Ethical Dilemmas and Decisions in Criminal Justice

You live next door to an Arab family, and you hear the husband talking negatively about the United States. Your friends at work tell you that you should report him to the police because he might be a terrorist. What would you do? Why? Georgia says that she would observe the man and the house to watch and take notes on what was going on and if her suspicions went further she would call the police. But I personally believe that I would go ahead and report what I had heard that way when I do find more evidence I can turn it in to the police so they have evidence against him instead of just going on one mishap that they know of.…

Clergy Abuse In The 1960s And 1970s

There have always been reports of clergy abuse but the rate escalated between the 1960s and 1970s, with an increased quantity of abuse occurring to males 11 to 17 years of age. After reaching the pinnacle in 1970s, the number of incidents declined throughout the 1980s and 1990s. Contributing factors to the abuse are considered to be "poor screening and training of priests" (Bono, 2016).…

Child Sexual Abuse and Father Flynn

It’s safe to say that the Catholic Church does not have the best reputation when it comes to sexual harassment and child molestation accusations. Cases such as these have been coming up for years but all seem to have similar outcomes. The priest typically gets a slap on the wrist, gets moved to another parish, and the issue is never spoken of again. In some of the more controversial cases, the priest is removed from the priesthood simply to get his name away from any association with the church because the church is known to do anything it can to cover up such accusations and rumors. This is no different for Father Flynn in the book Doubt, where he is accused of making sexual advances on an eighth grade boy that attends the school that he works in. He is accused by the principle of the school, Sister Aloysius, who is convinced he is guilty of giving the young boy wine from the sacristy and making inappropriate advances on him after doing so. Sister Aloysius may not have real evidence but based on Father Flynn’s behavior, his interest in boys with little to no friends, and his guilty conscience, it is easy to see that he is in fact guilty.…

Joseph's Vignette: Case Study

The ethical dilemma in the Joseph vignette is that the supervisor suspected the abuse and is asking the social worker, in this case me, to uncover the abuse. Birkenmaier, J., Berg-Weger, M., & Dewees, M.P. (2013) stress that “relationships that involve child or elder abuse or neglect, exploitation of older adults, and intimate partner violence were once considered private family issues outside the jurisdiction of the law or of any public sector interest” (p.59). The dilemma arises in deciphering if this is a private or public…

Pope Benedict Xvi Research Paper

For everyone worried that the election of a new Pope might signal a negative change in the Vatican's attitude about the sex-abuse scandal, it eases us to know that just before the death of John Paul, Cardinal Ratzinger ordered a reopening of a case that has been ignored for many years and one that he had personally put on hold in 1999 (Borse 2). Ratzinger's re-activation has resulted in a visit by the Prosecutor for the CDF, Father Scicluna, who was dispatched by Ratzinger himself to Mexico, the U.S. and Spain, to interview the original victims and gather what is now being described by some as new evidence from others who have not spoken to the Vatican about the case (Borse…

Essay On Mexican American Cultural Practices

Most Mexicans are Roman Catholic, and a smaller amount is Protestant. For many Mexican Americans, the Catholic Church plays an instrumental role in keeping families close and preserving Mexican culture. It’s also a great tool in maintaining the strength of local Mexican American communities. When unauthorized Mexican immigrants arrive in America, they are met with an unfamiliar culture and environment. However, one place they can seek solace from this new and scary situation is at church. By attending Mass and participating in church services and community, unauthorized immigrants can feel a sense of “home” and comfort. (Flores & Carey,…

Essay On Test Fairness

Following administration, and scoring of the test the next step is to perform an interpretation of the test. While interpreting the test the interpreter may find that, there are a few test bias that may have caused the scores to be high or low within a certain group causing the test to be unfair. Test bias and test fairness are two topics that individuals will continue to debate for years to come. Salkind (2013) described Test fairness as a very sensitive of use of examinations, quizzes, tests, etc. and social values and judgements are two influences in clarifying the results of test scores (Salkind, 2013, p. 294). However, Salkind (2013) described Test bias as an inconsistency in test scores between various groups due to factors that are irrelevant…

Argumentative Essay: Should The Court System Be Equal?

Modern society hinges upon the concept of true equality throughout daily life. So why should the court system not be equal as well? With the re-institution of trial by combat the playing field that is the courts would once again be equal. No longer would those with greater finances win a court dispute every time simply because they can afford better lawyers. Now should people wish to proceed by normal means they can, trial by combat is an optional choice to settle the dispute in question. Also should a person wish to invoke trial by combat but they are physically unable to do so they can call for a champion to fight in their place. Is this not what equal means, for both sides to have the same chances of winning regardless of where they come from or what their history is?…

Essay On Discrimination In The Workplace

One of the oldest and most often type of discrimination is related to the age of a person. Irrespective of the fact that, it happens in every country & in every system, but mostly at workplace. It has been observed that people beyond a certain age develop a certain type of complex from their younger counterparts about their skills, their needs in the same organization.…

Latino Immigrants

woman help, and the social worker reports her legal status to the INS, the woman runs the risk of…

Pro Immigration Law

Sister Helen Chaska was walking around in her hometown of Oregon doing missionary work when Maximiliano Esparza—illegal immigrant for Mexico—raped her and then strangled her with her rosary beads (Crime Victims). In another cases three young boy s, two of age 9 and the other age 10, were brutally killed by two illegal immigrants. One of the young boys was beheaded while the other two almost beheaded; the children also suffered from blunt force trauma and asphyxiation (Crime Victims). Immigrants such as Esparaza and the killers of the 3 young boys have no compassion or care for Americans i.e. 9/11. A majority of the violence that occurs in cities is committed by immigrants but once they are caught they are deported back to their country of origin.…

Just And Unjust Laws Essay

In Martin Luther King Jr.’s “Letter from Birmingham City Jail”, King talks about how to know the difference between just and unjust laws. He states, “Any law that uplifts human personality is just. Any law that degrades human personality is unjust”(Shafer-Landau 408). King believed that unjust laws promote disharmony and that these laws essentially destroy human personality, while just laws uplift personality. In his opinion, he believed that laws were characterized as just laws if they were helping to make an individual better as a person, if it did not meet those standards it was considered to be an unjust law. An unjust law is a “code that is out of harmony with the moral law”(Shafer-Landau 408) essentially meaning that an unjust law is a law that is…

A big house, nice cars and a loving family to share it all with; that is everyones aspiration in life. Well that dream is extremely difficult to achieve when working in the fields of Mexico for fifteen dollars a day picking tomatoes in the burning afternoon sun. Everyone deserves an equal chance to pursue their dreams but unfortunately this is not reality. which then forces people to take matters into their own hands. Illegal immigration is the most controversial topic in todays society. Some say it has a negative effect on the US, while others understand the devastating situations that these families are desperately trying to escape. These people are not here on a crime rampage, they are here seeking a better way to provide for their families. They are not criminals. They are here in hope of a positive outcome for future generations.…

Related Topics

  • Christianity
  • The Crucible

IMAGES

  1. Topic 9

    essay on procedural fairness

  2. Procedural-fairness-guidelines

    essay on procedural fairness

  3. Unit 6 Procedural Fairness (notes)

    essay on procedural fairness

  4. Procedural Fairness

    essay on procedural fairness

  5. (PDF) Procedural Fairness and Compliance With the Law

    essay on procedural fairness

  6. Pdf procedural fairness

    essay on procedural fairness

VIDEO

  1. Police Legitimacy & Procedural Justice

  2. “PROCEDURAL FAIRNESS” group 5

  3. Employment Law: Disciplinary Hearings

  4. How to Improve Fairness in AI

  5. Procedural Fairness Letter and Visa Documentation Tips

  6. Webinar

COMMENTS

  1. Procedural fairness: Between human rights law and social psychology

    Procedural justice refers to 'the judgments about the fairness of procedures used to make decisions'. 17 Thus, what is used as the basis for understanding what constitutes a fair procedure are persons' subjective perceptions. 18 Sometimes, the term 'perceived procedural justice' is used to emphasise this aspect.

  2. PDF PROCEDURAL FAIRNESS

    See alsoDavid B. Rottman, Adhere to Procedural Fairness Principles Throughout the Justice System, 6 CRIM. & PUB. POL'Y 835, 835 (2007). 11. WHY PEOPLE OBEY, supra note 5, at 23. nomenon exists.6 Thus, procedural fairness is a critical part of understanding how the public interprets their experience with the court system and translates that ...

  3. 5 Procedural Fairness in the English Common Law

    Procedural fairness is the modern concept, and only on rare occasions is reference made to its predecessor, due process. But on close inspection, it is clear that the two ideas cover the same ground; procedural fairness is a wider concept, but the core idea common to both is that certain procedures are needed to give effect to the ends of ...

  4. Judicial Review and Procedural Fairness in Administrative Law: I

    of "procedural fairness".2 In late 1978, however, the Supreme Court of Canada embraced the "procedural fairness" thesis,3 and its judg-ment has initiated a new creative period in the law of judicial review of administrative action.4. One of the leading advocates of the "fairness" approach is

  5. Full article: Whose procedural fairness?

    The idea of procedural fairness is a fundamental building block of the contemporary understanding of administrative justice. It is the basic notion that, putting aside the outcome, the way a public decision is made about a person or group matters to whether we deem that decision to be fair and legitimate. Traditional thinking on procedural ...

  6. Procedural Fairness

    Procedural fairness is then considered in its relationship to standards of fair treatment. Finally, the notions of fair treatment and procedural fairness are placed in their social context and a critique is offered of some of the empirical research into common perceptions of procedural fairness.

  7. Procedural Fairness

    The object of discussion in this chapter is the contemporary form of the second of the two rules of natural justice mentioned in the introduction to Chapter 2: audi alteram partem.In today's administrative law lexicon, audi alteram partem has become 'procedural fairness' or the 'duty of fairness'. The basic principle of these interchangeable terms is that an individual is entitled to ...

  8. PDF Procedural Fairness

    procedural fairness, and to the further danger of impermissibly broadening the scope of the principle, leaving it somewhat amorphous and undefined. The conclusion it was not fair becomes also the process of reasoning. For this reason, in order properly to understand the practical application of the requirements

  9. Public Law Essentials 05: Procedural fairness

    Procedural fairness in administrative decision-making relates to the fairness of the procedure by which a decision is made. A decision will be regarded as fair where it is made in accordance with statute and the requirements of natural justice. The two primary rules of natural justice are the 'hearing rule' and the 'bias rule'.

  10. Procedural Fairness in Administrative Decision-making: Approach of The

    2017] Procedural Fairness in Administrative Decision-Making... 337 stipulation and espoused to f or mula te a f air ness jurispr udence tha t a decision af fecting the civil rights of persons should be made only after following the rules of natural justice. The juristic tec hniques of appl ying the doctrine of na tur al justice with its g rowing

  11. Fundamentals of Procedural Fairness

    The Fundamentals of Procedural Justice. Professor Tom Tyler of Yale Law School and Chief Judge Jeffrey Kremers from Milwaukee introduce the concept of procedural justice and discuss how improved perceptions of fairness can yield significant benefits, including improved compliance with court orders, reduced recidivism, and improved public trust ...

  12. (PDF) Procedural fairness as constitutional justice: an essay on Hans

    This paper explores the effect that conformity to the rule of law has on the ends which might legitimately be pursued within a legal system. The neat distinction between formal and substantive conceptions of the rule of law will be challenged: even apparently formal conceptions necessarily affect the content of law and necessarily entail the protection of certain fundamental rights.

  13. Procedural Fairness

    Welcome! Procedural fairness (also referred to as procedural justice) is an evidence-based practice reliably associated with higher levels of compliance with and greater amounts of satisfaction with decisions by authority figures. Increasingly, national judicial organizations have recognized the importance of promoting procedural fairness.

  14. Basic Elements of Procedural Fairness « Formative Law

    There are essentially 2 principles and they are in Latin and the English is: 1. Number one is the right to be heard (this is one procedural fairness principle); and, the 2nd is the right to be judged impartially. Now these procedures manifest in many different ways. Let's go through the examples of how procedural fairness may work in ...

  15. Topic 9

    Procedural fairness (or as it is known at CL) generally consists of two components: (1) Audi Alteram Partem: the right to a hearing. (2) Nemo iudex in sua causa: the rule against bias also expressed as person can be a judge in their own In Van Huyssteen NO v Minister of Environmental Affairs: the HC (under s24 IC) held that s24 (now s33) of the ...

  16. Judicial Review and Procedural Fairness in Administrative Law: II

    The essay will conclude with the formulation of. a theory of procedural review of administrative action and an institu-. tional model which exploits the possibilities of the emerging doctrine. of fairness. I. Towards a theory of implied procedural review. The law of procedural review in Canada has not developed.

  17. Public Law

    The worry with this however, as shown in the essay, is that in both the appeal process and the initial judgement an impartial decision maker is absent, defeating the purpose of procedural fairness. Nor is there access to legal representation which could be the difference in finding a student guilty or innocent of the offence in question.

  18. Principles Of Fairness Application Example Essay

    Disclaimer: This essay has been written by a law student and not by our expert law writers. View examples of our professional work here. Principles Of Fairness Application Example Essay. Info: 3016 words (12 pages) Example Law Essay Published: 6th Aug 2019. The Application of the principles of fairness. Example Essay.

  19. Procedural Fairness in South African Regulatory Decisions: Transparency

    Procedural fairness, also known as natural justice, refers to the procedures used by regulatory bodies to ensure decisions are made fairly, impartially and reasonably. It's a fundamental aspect of the administrative process in South Africa, ensuring that the rights of individuals and organizations are protected.

  20. Procedural fairness essay

    1 I INTRODUCTION The duty to afford procedural fairness is the basic precept of good administrative decision making. Courts safeguard procedural fairness as it promotes public confidence in decision makers, provides dignity to individuals and fosters democracy through participation Since Kioa v West,2 it is assumed that there is a common law duty to extend fairness to decisions where an ...

  21. Overview of Procedural Due Process in Criminal Cases

    Jump to essay-3 While the following essays focus primarily on Supreme Court litigation challenging state criminal procedures, some of the cases cited discuss federal criminal procedures. See also Amdt5.6.1 Overview of Due Process Procedural Requirements. The doctrine of incorporation applies only to state government action in criminal cases ...

  22. Procedural Fairness

    Procedural Fairness. 1371 Words6 Pages. When it is talked about procedural fairness what is meant is equal treatment by the law and the administration, this applies to both people and corporations. When an issue arises with respect to that principle, one of the pillars of administrative law is usually the solution and that is judicial review.

  23. The Legal Approach to Procedural Fairness

    Abstract. This chapter describes and analyses the general judicial approach to procedural fairness. It examines a number of issues: the tests developed by English law as to who is entitled to fair procedures; the extent to which abstract principles are translated into more detailed procedural rules; and the general judicial approach to exactly what procedural fairness requires and how those ...

  24. Essay On Procedural Fairness

    Essay On Procedural Fairness. "If we have no peace, it is because we have forgotten that we belong to each other."-. Mother Teresa (Quotes About Humanity, n.d.) Peace, serenity, and security is what all of us human aim to achieve, but we must not forget the rules, ethics that we need to obey to help us maintain a healthy society.