An Analytic Framework for Research on Judicial Decision-Making

  • First Online: 04 November 2022

Cite this chapter

Book cover

  • Wessel Wijtvliet 17  

Part of the book series: Economic Analysis of Law in European Legal Scholarship ((EALELS,volume 14))

326 Accesses

Proposition about legal actors like judges inevitably rely on assumptions about the type and extent of knowledge researchers can acquire of social reality. Seemingly innocuous claims like “legal rules influence the choices judges make”, “political preferences drive judgments” or “the case disposition makes sense in light of the applicable rules” all stem from fundamentally distinct epistemological positions. Considering their ubiquity in legal scholarship, knowledge of these differences is essential for academic lawyers who consume or produce research on judicial decision-making. The current chapter draws from the philosophy of social science to outline a framework of four such positions. It subsequently applies the resultant typology to a wide variety of research strands in judicial studies, linking the epistemic tenets to the practice of legal scholarship. The philosophical positions differ with respect to the way in which academic lawyers can either causally explain or give interpretative meaning to the relation between judges and legal rules. This novel overview helps researchers understand and weigh the relevant differences between various statements about judges and obtain insight into the often-implicit assumptions behind their own work. As a specification of more general philosophical principles, the framework applies to other types of legal actors as well.

  • Philosophy of social science
  • Epistemology
  • Legal scholarship
  • Judicial decision-making

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
  • Durable hardcover edition

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Hollis ( 1994 ).

Morton ( 2003 ).

Vanberg ( 2002 ).

I am aware that legal scholarship is generally associated with the doctrinal analysis of legal norms and not the relationship between these norms and their environmental influences (Samuel 2009 , pp. 438–442). Be that as it may, whenever legal scholars focus on norms vis-à-vis actors they stray away from doctrinarism into the realm of social science. The chapter exactly and exclusively revolves around that particular situation.

Alternative approaches include Campbell ( 1981 ) (uses a much wider typology); Kincaid ( 1996 ) (presents the scientific or causal study of the meaning people attribute to social action under the rubric interpretation); Reed ( 2011 ) (attempts to integration causal explanation and interpretation in sociology by the use of theory); Rosenberg ( 2012 ) (discusses functionalism more thoroughly); Risjord ( 2014 ) (applies a more topical approach).

Hollis generally uses the term understanding to refer to what others might call interpretation . I will use the latter term throughout this chapter for two reasons. First, interpretation is more commonly used than understanding . Second, understanding may evoke similarity to the wholly separate scientific enterprise of understanding the natural world (De Regt 2017 ). On a separate note, the use of interpretation should be distinguished from interpretation as textual analysis commonly used by lawyers as well as linguists and theologians.

Rosenberg and McIntyre ( 2020 ), p. 40.

An example would be Henderson ( 1993 ). Naturalism in the philosophy of social science should be distinguished from the concept in the philosophy of science. In the latter context, naturalism refers to the position that the entire world is made up of physical matter or physical fields and nothing else (Rosenberg and McIntyre 2020 , pp. 228–235).

Naturalism is a label that encompasses philosophies that may still diverge on numerous matters. Although naturalism succeeded empiricism (Rosenberg and McIntyre 2020 , p. 228), not everything science studies is observable. Thus some scientists assume their most basic variable and inspect these by measuring their effects. However, philosophers disagree whether science should aim to provide a true description of the entire world or only of its observable part (Okasha 2002 , pp. 58–76). Social scientists face a similar difficulty. In the past, this led the behaviorists in psychology to focus solely on that which is actually and indisputably visible, namely behavior of individuals and not their memory, reasoning or will (Hunt 2007 , pp. 274–317).

Dworkin ( 2005 ), p. 3.

Baum ( 2010 ), p. 4.

Risjord ( 2014 ), pp. 154–155, 173–174.

The extent to which exceptionless regularities form the basis of natural laws features prominently in debates between philosophers of science (Carroll 2016 ). Even in the possible absence of natural laws, statistical regularities improve the testability of scientific propositions (Rosenberg and McIntyre 2020 , pp. 75–88).

Obviously matters are different in biology. For a good philosophical introduction see (Dennett 1996 ).

Opponents of what may be dubbed scientific imperialism often point out that application of scientific methods to the social domain has a dehumanizing effect on the study objects or negatively affects the social institutions it studies (Rosenberg and McIntyre 2020 , pp. 22–23). For instance, a frequently heard complaint among legal scholars is that studying the influence of political preferences on judicial decision-making corrodes the legitimacy of the judiciary (Gibson and Caldeira 2011 ). Whatever the validity of the criticism, I consider it a normative-consequentialist and not an epistemological argument against a particular philosophical position in social science, which goes beyond the scope of the chapter.

Taylor ( 1971 ).

For a broader discussion of interpretation see Kincaid ( 1996 ), pp. 191–221.

Hayek ( 1978 , 1980 ).

Scriven ( 1956 ).

Hart ( 1998 ), p. 141.

Hart’s entire argument rests on “It is surely evident that,” which is no argument at all (Leiter 2001 , pp. 299–300).

As always, there are exceptions to this generalization. Alex Rosenberg defends the position that this folk understanding of the mind is incorrect and that most of these classes do not, in fact, exist at all. See Rosenberg ( 2019 ).

Rosenberg ( 2012 ), pp. 38–42.

There are plenty of examples that deviate from the current division. The work of (Giddens 1997 ) attempts to merge the two levels of analysis. Max Weber stresses the idealist aspect of social action in which subjective understanding is pivotal. Despite this seemingly interpretivist inclination, he also tasks sociological understanding with viewing action in terms of common social symbols, which means understanding it as an activity characteristic for a particular social context. Importantly, if an action is typical for a particular society, then it becomes possible to uncover patterns of behavior, which would move his epistemological outlook into the direction of causal explanation (Campbell 1981 , pp. 169–174, 188). Bruno Latour deploys a framework in which humans and non-humans, structures and individuals, explanation and interpretation all play a role in making social phenomena understandable (de Vries 2016 , pp. 83–113).

Durkheim ( 2014 ), p. 102.

Durkheim ( 2014 ), p. 20.

Durkheim ( 2014 ), p. 86.

Durkheim ( 2014 ), p. 129.

Durkheim ( 2014 ), pp. 90, 97–98.

Durkheim ( 2014 ), p. 21.

Durkheim ( 2014 ), p. xxi.

Scott Gordon ( 1997 ), pp. 445–446.

Deflem ( 2008 ), p. 58.

Durkheim ( 2014 ), p. 90.

Durkheim ( 2014 ), p. 34.

Deflem ( 2008 ), p. 62.

Collins ( 1982 ), pp. 2–3.

Deflem ( 2008 ), pp. 24–28.

There are Marxist scholars who interpret Marx to have meant that lower level factors affect these forces as well (Ollman 1998 ).

Hollis ( 1994 ), pp. 6–7; Marx ( 1904 ), pp. 10–11.

Marx and Friedrich ( 1998 ), p. 42.

Durkheim ( 2014 ), p. 111.

Mill ( 1988 ), p. 65.

Mill ( 1988 ), p. 104.

Hollis ( 1994 ), p. 10–11.

Positive science is related to the term positivism and can therefore be confusing. Positivism in the realm of social science has a broader meaning because it often encompasses all approaches that apply the scientific method to the social domain, including holism and Weber’s naturalism that relies on the subjective meaning of actors (Hollis 1994 , 42). Positivism in legal scholarship has a different meaning altogether and refers to the two-pronged philosophical belief that (1) what is to count is law is a social fact; and (2) that law and morality are not necessarily connected (Coleman and Leiter 2010 ).

Hollis ( 1994 ), p. 42.

The description involves the path from theory to observation, not the epistemological position of individual.

Hollis ( 1994 ), pp. 43–44, 49, 64. Although prediction is not necessarily similar to explanation, the positivist Milton Friedman defends a position in which prediction validates a hypothesis and forms the basis of explanation. See (Friedman 2001 ).

Hobbes ( 2008 ), p. 8.

Other classical economics rejected such an approach to economics. They dismissed the use of theory as a driver for research and, instead, opted for an inductive approach on the basis of historical analysis. The accumulation of facts would, according to this school of thought, generate, over time, enough information to construct laws of nature (Scott Gordon 1997 , p. 203).

Scott Gordon ( 1997 ), pp. 202–203.

Scott Gordon ( 1997 ), p. 265.

Smith ( 2009 ), p. 453.

Bentham ( 1879 ), p. 14.

Hollis ( 1994 ), pp. 51–53. Referral to a shared human nature does not mean that all human in all situations act in similar fashion. Utilitarianism after Bentham commences from the much more pragmatic premise that people in general act in a similar fashion when confronted with comparable social situations (Scott Gordon 1997 , p. 252). Some present-day economists still stress methodological individualism as the guiding principle in their discipline while acknowledging the contingency of the social environment, taking seriously contextual differences and negating claims of universality (Rodrik 2016 , pp. 112,181–182).

Elster ( 2015 ), p. 235.

Elster ( 1986 ), p. 4.

Hollis ( 1987 ), pp. 15–28.

Hollis ( 1987 ), pp. 29–46; Hollis ( 1994 ), pp. 115–117.

Winch ( 1990 ), pp. 87–89.

Hollis ( 1994 ), pp. 151–157.

Hollis ( 1994 ), pp. 159–160.

Hollis ( 1994 ), pp. 143, 147.

Warnke ( 1987 ), pp. 48–49.

Hollis ( 1994 ), p. 145.

Hollis ( 1994 ), pp. 165–167, 171.

Hollis ( 1994 ), p. 172.

Hollis ( 1994 ), pp. 174–175.

Hollis ( 1994 ), pp. 164, 168.

Leiter ( 2010 ), p. 111.

Montesquieu ( 1989 ), pp. 157–158.

Montesquieu ( 1989 ), p. 163.

Pound ( 1908 ), p. 608.

Frank ( 1963 ), pp. 127–128.

Neuborne ( 1992 ), p. 421.

Vanberg ( 2002 ), p. 129.

See for instance Segal and Spaeth ( 2002 ), pp. 44–85.

For instance, Tamanaha takes stock of the way in which judges have, for more than a century, been candid about the limited guidance legal norms offer for judgment (Tamanaha 2009 ).

Baum ( 2010 ), p. 3.

Kincaid ( 1996 ), p. 219.

Elliott ( 1972 ).

Smith and Hogg ( 2008 ).

Gillman and Clayton ( 1999 ), p. 6.

Clayton and Gillman ( 1999 ), p. 5.

Gillman and Clayton ( 1999 ), pp. 4–5; Kahn ( 1999 ), p. 196.

Clayton ( 1999 ), p. 31; Gillman ( 1999 ), pp. 74–76; Kahn ( 1999 ), p. 175.

Whittington ( 2000 ), p. 615.

Whittington ( 2000 ), pp. 613–616.

Richards and Kritzer ( 2002 ), p. 307.

Richards and Kritzer ( 2002 ), p. 308.

Richards and Kritzer ( 2002 ), p. 309.

Richards and Kritzer ( 2002 ), pp. 305–306.

Cross ( 1997 ), p. 326.

Segal ( 2008 ), p. 19.

Horwitz ( 1992 ), p. 1.

Pritchett ( 1948 ), p. 16.

Segal and Spaeth ( 2002 ), p. 86.

Spaeth ( 2008 ), p. 753.

See for examples outside the US context Voeten ( 2007 ); Voeten ( 2008 ); Alarie and Green ( 2009 ); Weiden ( 2011 ); Hanretty ( 2012 ); Hanretty ( 2013 ); Llanos and Lemos ( 2013 ).

Epstein and Knight ( 1998 ), p. 11–12.

Ferejohn and Weingast ( 1991 ), pp. 571, 574; Baum ( 1997 ), pp. 21, 25; Kastellec ( 2017 ).

Epstein and Knight ( 1998 ), pp. 22–23. Over time, this narrow focus has increasingly led to sharp criticism (Epstein and Knight 2013 ).

Epstein and Knight ( 1998 ), pp. 11–17.

Neither environmental constraints nor the relevance of rules pulls the strategic model away from methodological individualism. Environmental constraints consist of the goal-seeking behavior of other individuals operating in the environment of an adjacent political body. Rules and norms may seem more reminiscent of holism. Be that as it may, actors do not abide by rules because of their socialization or the immanent effect they radiate. Deviation from rules merely could lead to the expectation that external actors will respond in a fashion that hampers the attainment of goals. Again, the ability to write convincing legal treaties that establish a decision strongly within the legal system and conceal its subjective nature determines the degree to which judges are free to act on preferences. This perspective also raises pertinent questions about lower court decision-making. Scholars traditionally acknowledge that legal indeterminacy and the sway of rules play out differently on the level of lower and appellate courts (see for instance Twining ( 2020 )). However, the difference in and of itself does not arbitrate whether the decisions of lower court judges are caused by precedents formulated on a higher level (holism) or by their fear of being overruled on appeal (individualism).

Epstein and Knight ( 1998 ), pp. 145–157.

Posner ( 1993 ), p. 39; see also Schauer ( 1999 ).

Epstein et al. ( 2013 ), pp. 30–50. Ironically, two critics remark that for all its theoretical ambitions, the empirical practice of the book mainly involves testing the influence of ideology on judging (Cameron and Kornhauser 2015 ).

Baum ( 1997 ).

Baum ( 2008 ), p. 21.

Baum ( 2008 ), p. 60.

Baum ( 2008 ), p. 158.

Siems and Mac Síthigh ( 2012 ), pp. 654–655.

Rosenberg ( 2012 ), pp. 44–45; Risjord ( 2014 ), p. 46.

Leiter ( 2003 ), p. 18.

For a comprehensive introduction into the debate, see Shapiro ( 2007 ).

Hart ( 1958 ), p. 599.

Bayles ( 1990 ), pp. 30, 34.

I use the phrase implication because legal positivists generally remain agnostic about the relation between legal norms and actual judicial behavior (Leiter 1999 , p. 1152).

Hart ( 1998 ), p. 98.

Hart ( 1998 ), p. 137.

Hart ( 1998 ), p. 138.

Hart ( 1998 ), p. 249.

The first part of the sentence makes a causal argument while the second part is an example of an interpretative claim.

Dworkin ( 2010 ), p. 13.

Dworkin ( 2010 ), p. 90.

Dworkin ( 2010 ), p. 64.

Dworkin is thus not a moral realist in the sense that he proposes the existence of a moral order as a matter-of-fact, from which the meaning of legal terms can be deduced (Dworkin 2010 , p. 86).

Leiter ( 1996 ), p. 255.

Kelsen ( 1949 ), pp. 132–134.

Kelsen ( 1949 ), p. 134.

Barak ( 2006 ), pp. 4, 20–21.

Barak ( 2006 ), p. 311.

Barak ( 2006 ), p. 314.

Sunstein ( 2015 ), pp. 1–2.

Sunstein ( 2015 ), pp. 37–39, 41.

Jones and Sarat 2017 .

In The Simpsons, season 28, episode 2, Mr. Burns uses a virtual reality device to experience a life in which he would have had a family. The artificial intelligence involved allows him to design his children in his image, leading him to exclaim ‘It’s too beautiful. Like a Supreme Court full of Scalias.’ The tongue-in-cheek reference not only testifies to Scalia’s reach beyond the legal profession into popular culture but also illustrates the role an individual can play in shaping normative structures.

Rosenberg ( 2012 ), pp. 38, 42.

Kincaid ( 1996 ), p. 93.

Jost ( 2012 ), pp. 58–68.

Hayek ( 1978 ), p. 40.

Carroll ( 2017 ).

Carroll ( 2017 ), p. 3.

Carroll ( 2017 ), pp. 379–380.

Alarie B, Green A (2009) Policy preference change and appointments to the Supreme Court of Canada. Osgoode Hall Law J 47. HeinOnline: 1

Google Scholar  

Barak A (2006) The judge in a democracy. Princeton University Press, Princeton

Baum L (1997) The puzzle of judicial behavior. Analytical perspectives on politics. University of Michigan Press, Ann Arbor

Baum L (2008) Judges and their audiences. A perspective on judicial behavior. Princeton University Press, Princeton

Baum L (2010) Motivation and judicial behavior: expanding the scope of inquiry. In: Klein DE, Mitchell G (eds) The psychology of judicial decision making, American Psychology-Law Society Series. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 3–25

Bayles M (1990) What is jurisprudence about? Theories, definitions, concepts, or conceptions of law? Philos Top 18:23

Bentham J (1879) An introduction to the principles of morals and legislation. Clarendon Press

Cameron CM, Kornhauser LA (2015) Rational choice attitudinalism? A review of Epstein, Landes and Posner’s the behavior of federal judges: a theoretical and empirical study of rational choice. Eur J Law Econ:1–20

Campbell T (1981) Seven theories of human society. Clarendon Press/Oxford University Press, Oxford, New York

Carroll JW (2016) Laws of nature. In: Zalta EN (ed) The Stanford Encyclopedia of philosophy, fall 2016. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University

Carroll S (2017) The big picture. On the origins of life, meaning and the universe itself. Oneworld Publications, London

Clayton CW (1999) The supreme court and political jurisprudence: new and old institutionalism. In: Clayton CW, Gillman H (eds) Supreme court decision-making: new institutionalist approaches. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, pp 15–41

Clayton CW, Gillman H (1999) Introduction. In: Gillman H, Clayton CW (eds) The Supreme Court in American politics: new institutionalist interpretations. University Press of Kansas, Lawrence, Kan, pp 1–11

Coleman JL, Leiter B (2010) Legal positivism. In Patterson DM (ed) A companion to philosophy of law and legal theory. Blackwell Companions to Philosophy 8. Wiley-Blackwell, Chichester, pp 228–248

Collins H (1982) Marxism and law. Marxist introductions. Clarendon Press/Oxford University Press, Oxford/New York

Cross FB (1997) Political science and the new legal realism: a case of unfortunate interdisciplinary ignorance. Northwest Univ Law Rev 92:251. US method

de Regt HW (2017) Understanding scientific understanding. Oxford University Press, New York

de Vries G (2016) Bruno Latour. Polity Press, Cambridge

Deflem M (2008) Sociology of law: visions of a scholarly tradition. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

Dennett DC (1996) Darwin’s dangerous idea: evolution and the meanings of life. Penguin Science, Penguin Books, London

Durkheim E (2014) The rules of sociological method: and selected texts on sociology and its method. Lukes S (ed) (Halls WD, Trans.). Free Press, New York

Dworkin R (2005) Freedom’s law: the moral reading of the American constitution. Reprint. Oxford University Press, Oxford

Dworkin R (2010) Law’s empire. Hart, Oxford

Elliott P (1972) The sociology of the professions. Macmillan Education UK, London

Elster J (ed) (1986) Rational choice. Readings in social and political theory. New York University Press, Washington Square, NY

Elster J (2015) Explaining social behavior: more nuts and bolts for the social sciences, Revised edn. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

Epstein L, Knight J (1998) The choices justices make. CQ Press, Washington

Epstein L, Knight J (2013) Reconsidering judicial preferences. Annu Rev Polit Sci 16:11–31

Epstein L, Landes WM, Posner RA (2013) The behavior of Federal Judges. A theoretical and empirical study of rational choice. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

Ferejohn J, Weingast B (1991) Limitation of statutes: strategic statutory interpretation. Georgetown Law J 80:565

Frank J (1963) Law and the modern mind. Garden City Doubleday

Friedman M (2001) The methodology of positive economics. In: Friedman M (ed) Essays in positive economics. Univ. of Chicago Press, Chicago, pp 3–43

Gibson JL, Caldeira GA (2011) Has legal realism damaged the legitimacy of the U.S. Supreme Court? Law Soc Rev 45:195–219. Legitimacy

Giddens A (1997) New rules of sociological method: a positive critique of interpretative sociologies, 2nd rev edn. repr. Polity Press, Cambridge

Gillman H (1999) The court as an idea, not a building (or a game): interpretive institutionalism and the analysis of supreme court decision-making. In: Gillman H, Clayton CW (eds) Supreme court decision-making: new institutionalist approaches. University Press of Kansas, Lawrence, Kan, pp 65–87

Gillman H, Clayton CW (1999) Beyond judicial attitudes: institutional approaches to supreme court decision-making. In: Clayton CW, Gillman H (eds) Supreme court decision-making: new institutionalist approaches. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, pp 1–12

Hanretty C (2012) Dissent in Iberia: the ideal points of justices on the Spanish and Portuguese constitutional tribunals. Eur J Polit Res 51:671–692

Hanretty C (2013) The decisions and ideal points of British law lords. Br J Polit Sci 43:703–716

Hart HLA (1958) Positivism and the separation of law and morals. Harv Law Rev 71:593

Hart HLA (1998) In: Bulloch PA, Raz J (eds) The concept of law, 2nd edn. Clarendon Law Series, Clarendon Press, Oxford

Hayek FA (1978) The theory of complex phenomena. In: Studies in philosophy, politics and economics. Routledge & Kegan Paul, London

Hayek FA (1980) The facts of social sciences. In: Individualism and economic order, paperback. Univ. of Chicago Press, Chicago, pp 57–76

Henderson DK (1993) Interpretation and explanation in the human sciences. SUNY series in the philosophy of the social sciences. State University of New York Press, Albany

Hobbes T (2008) Leviathan. In: Gaskin JCA (ed) Oxford World’s classics. Oxford University Press, Oxford

Hollis M (1987) The cunning of reason. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge [Cambridgeshire]; New York

Hollis M (1994) The philosophy of social science: an introduction. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

Horwitz MJ (1992) The transformation of American law, 1870–1960: the crisis of legal orthodoxy. Oxford University Press, New York

Hunt MM (2007) The story of psychology, 2nd Anchor Books edn. Anchor Books, New York

Jones BC, Sarat A (2017) Justices as “Sacred Symbols”: Antonin Scalia and the cultural life of the law. Br J Am Leg Stud 6:7–23

Jost JT (2012) The end of the end of ideology. In: Hanson J (ed) Ideology, psychology, and law, Series in Political Psychology. Oxford University Press, Oxford; New York, pp 32–77

Kahn R (1999) Institutional norms and supreme court decision-making: the Rehnquist court on privacy and religion. In: Gillman H, Clayton CW (eds) Supreme court decision-making: new institutionalist approaches. University Press of Kansas, Lawrence, Kan, pp 201–214

Kastellec J (2017) The judicial hierarchy: a review essay. Oxford Research Encyclopedia of Politics

Kelsen H (1949) General theory of law and state. The 20th century legal philosophy series. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

Kincaid H (1996) Philosophical foundations of the social sciences: analyzing controversies in social research. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

Leiter B (1996) Heidegger and the theory of adjudication. Yale Law J 106:253–282

Leiter B (1999) Positivism, formalism, realism. Columbia Law Rev 99:1138–1164

Leiter B (2001) Legal realism and legal positivism reconsidered*. Ethics 111:278–301

Leiter B (2003) Beyond the Hart/Dworkin debate: the methodology problem in jurisprudence symposium: has law moral foundations. Am J Jurisprud 48:17–52

Leiter B (2010) Legal formalism and legal realism: what is the issue? Legal Theory 16:111–133

Llanos M, Lemos LB (2013) Presidential preferences? The Supreme Federal Tribunal Nominations in Democratic Brazil. Latin American Politics and Society 55. Cambridge University Press, pp 77–105

Marx K (1904) A contribution to the critique of political economy (Stone NI, Trans.). Charles H. Kerr, Chicago

Marx K, Friedrich E (1998) The German ideology: including theses on Feuerbach and introduction to the critique of political economy. Great books in philosophy. Prometheus Books, Amherst

Mill JS (1988) The logic of the moral sciences. Open court classics. Open Court, La Salle

Montesquieu C (1989) The spirit of the laws. In: Cohler AM, Miller BC, Stone HS (eds) Cambridge texts in the history of political thought. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

Morton A (2003) A guide through the theory of knowledge, 3rd edn. Blackwell Pub, Malden

Neuborne B (1992) Of sausage factories and syllogism machines: formalism, realism, and exclusionary selection techniques. N Y Univ Law Rev 67:419

Okasha S (2002) Philosophy of science: a very short introduction. Very Short Introductions 67. Oxford University Press, Oxford

Ollman B (1998) Alienation: Marx’s conception of man in capitalist society, 2nd edn. repr. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

Posner RA (1993) What do judges and justices maximize--(the same thing everybody else does). Supreme Court Econ Rev 3:1

Pound R (1908) Mechanical Jurisprudence. Columbia Law Rev 8:605–623

Pritchett CH (1948) The Roosevelt court: a study in judicial politics and values, 1937–1947. The Macmillan Company, New York

Reed I (2011) Interpretation and social knowledge: on the use of theory in the human sciences. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago

Richards MJ, Kritzer HM (2002) Jurisprudential regimes in supreme court decision making. Am Polit Sci Rev 96:305–320

Risjord MW (2014) Philosophy of social science. A contemporary introduction. Routledge contemporary introductions to philosophy. Routledge, Taylor & Francis Group, New York

Rodrik D (2016) Economics rules: the rights and wrongs of the dismal science, 1st edn. Norton, New York

Rosenberg A (2012) Philosophy of social science, 4th edn. Westview Press, Boulder

Rosenberg A (2019) How history gets things wrong: the neuroscience of our addiction to stories. The MIT Press, Cambridge

Rosenberg A, McIntyre LC (2020) The philosophy of science: a contemporary introduction, 4th edn. Routledge, New York

Samuel G (2009) Interdisciplinarity and the authority paradigm: should law be taken seriously by scientists and social scientists? J Law Soc 36:431–459

Schauer F (1999) Incentives, reputation, and the inglorious determinants of judicial behavior. Univ Cincinnati Law Rev 68:615. US method

Scott Gordon H (1997) The history and philosophy of social science. Repr. Routledge, London

Scriven M (1956) A possible distinction between traditional scientific disciplines and the study of human behavior. In: Feigl H, Scriven M (eds) Foundations of science and the concepts of psychology and psychoanalysis, 330–339. Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science 1. University of Minnesota Press, Minnesota

Segal JA (2008) Judicial behavior. In: Whittington KE, Kelemen RD, Caldeira GA (eds) The Oxford handbook of law and politics, Oxford Handbooks of Political Science. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 19–33

Segal JA, Spaeth HJ (2002) The Supreme Court and the attitudinal model revisited. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

Shapiro SJ (2007) The ‘Hart–Dworkin’ debate: a short guide for the perplexed. In: Dworkin R (ed) Arthur Ripstein. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 22–55

Siems MM, Mac Síthigh D (2012) Mapping legal research. Camb Law J 71:651–676

Smith A (2009) An inquiry into the nature and causes of the wealth of nations. BiblioBazaar, LLC

Smith JR, Hogg MA (2008) Social identity and attitudes. In: Crano WD, Prislin R (eds) Attitudes and attitude change. Psychology Press, pp 337–361

Spaeth HJ (2008) Reflections about judicial politics. In: Whittington KE, Kelemen RD, Caldeira GA (eds) The Oxford handbook of law and politics, Oxford Handbooks of Political Science. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 752–766

Sunstein CR (2015) Constitutional personae. Inalienable rights series. Oxford University Press, New York

Tamanaha BZ (2009) Realism of judges past and present. Clev State Law Rev 57:77

Taylor CH (1971) Interpretation and the sciences of man. Rev Metaphys 25:3–51. JSTOR

Twining W (2020) Jurist in context. A memoir. Cambridge University Press

Vanberg G (2002) Law, political science and EU legal studies. An interdisciplinary project? Law, politics, and interdisciplinary work. Eur Union Polit 3:127–135. Legal method

Voeten E (2007) The politics of international judicial appointments: evidence from the European Court of Human Rights. Int Org 61

Voeten E (2008) The impartiality of international judges: evidence from the European court of human rights. Am Polit Sci Rev 102:417–433

Warnke G (1987) Gadamer: hermeneutics, tradition, and reason. Key contemporary thinkers. Polity Press, Cambridge

Weiden DL (2011) Judicial politicization, ideology, and activism at the High Courts of the United States, Canada, and Australia. Political Research Quarterly 64. Los Angeles Sage Publications Sage, pp 335–347

Whittington KE (2000) Once more unto the breach: post behavioralist approaches to judicial politics. Law Soc Inq 25:601–634

Winch P (1990) The idea of a social science and its relation to philosophy. Routledge, London

Download references

Author information

Authors and affiliations.

Centre for Legal Theory and Empirical Jurisprudence, Leuven, Belgium

Wessel Wijtvliet

You can also search for this author in PubMed   Google Scholar

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Wessel Wijtvliet .

Editor information

Editors and affiliations.

Jagiellonian University, Kraków, Poland

Piotr Bystranowski

University of Silesia in Katowice, Katowice, Poland

Bartosz Janik

Maciej Próchnicki

Additional information

Research Fellow at the Leuven Centre for Legal Theory and Empirical Jurisprudence. I would like to thank Toon Agten, Jitte Akkermans, Jan-Baptist Lemaire, Laura Ritter, Wolfgang Weigel and the editors for their useful suggestions regarding this chapter. Any mistakes in the text remain my own.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Wijtvliet, W. (2022). An Analytic Framework for Research on Judicial Decision-Making. In: Bystranowski, P., Janik, B., Próchnicki, M. (eds) Judicial Decision-Making. Economic Analysis of Law in European Legal Scholarship, vol 14. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-11744-2_7

Download citation

DOI : https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-11744-2_7

Published : 04 November 2022

Publisher Name : Springer, Cham

Print ISBN : 978-3-031-11743-5

Online ISBN : 978-3-031-11744-2

eBook Packages : Social Sciences Social Sciences (R0)

Share this chapter

Anyone you share the following link with will be able to read this content:

Sorry, a shareable link is not currently available for this article.

Provided by the Springer Nature SharedIt content-sharing initiative

  • Publish with us

Policies and ethics

  • Find a journal
  • Track your research

IMAGES

  1. Judge Job Description: Salary, Skills, & More

    a research scholar has to work as a judge

  2. How Many Years Does it Take to Become Judge

    a research scholar has to work as a judge

  3. The Graduate School of the Stowers Institute

    a research scholar has to work as a judge

  4. how to become a judge

    a research scholar has to work as a judge

  5. Research Scholar Job Description

    a research scholar has to work as a judge

  6. What is a Scholarly Source? Here are 7 Examples (2024)

    a research scholar has to work as a judge

VIDEO

  1. 🇨🇳🤯 PhD Christian Scholar ADMITS Bible has Errors❗#shorts

  2. Breaking: Dr.Ayesha Siddiqa explains the military, its businesses, and challenges Imran Khan pose

  3. High court #law #justice #court

  4. This is why you should NEVER judge an artists unfinished work 🤪 (sound by superraedizzle) #art

  5. Every legal system in the world has judges

  6. Specialists in legal research

COMMENTS

  1. An Analytic Framework for Research on Judicial Decision

    Considering their ubiquity in legal scholarship, knowledge of these differences is essential for academic lawyers who consume or produce research on judicial decision-making. The current chapter draws from the philosophy of social science to outline a framework of four such positions. It subsequently applies the resultant typology to a wide ...