• Search Menu
  • Advance Articles
  • Special Issues
  • Virtual Issues
  • Trending Articles
  • IMPACT Content
  • Author Guidelines
  • Submission Site
  • Open Access Options
  • Self-Archiving Policy
  • Author Resources
  • Read & Publish
  • Why Publish with JOPE?
  • About the Journal of Philosophy of Education
  • About The Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain
  • Editorial Board
  • Advertising & Corporate Services
  • Journals on Oxford Academic
  • Books on Oxford Academic

Issue Cover

Article Contents

  • INTRODUCTION
  • MORAL PRINCIPLES: HELP OR HINDRANCE?
  • MORAL PERCEPTION AND THE NEED FOR ATTENTION
  • EMOTIONS AND MORAL SENSITIVITY
  • ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS
  • < Previous

Moral sensitivity: The central question of moral education

  • Article contents
  • Figures & tables
  • Supplementary Data

Roger Marples, Moral sensitivity: The central question of moral education, Journal of Philosophy of Education , Volume 56, Issue 2, April 2022, Pages 342–355, https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-9752.12633

  • Permissions Icon Permissions

There is more to the moral life than mere adherence to a set of moral rules or principles to which the moral agent has autonomously subscribed. Something more fundamental is required for moral personhood, requiring explication in terms of ‘sensitive perception’ in relation to the particularities pertaining to any given set of circumstances meriting a moral response. The article addresses the importance of accuracy of conceptualisation, the need for attentiveness and sensitivity in the identification of moral salience, and concludes with the role of affect in this enterprise.

Email alerts

Citing articles via.

  • Recommend to Your Librarian
  • Advertising and Corporate Services
  • Journals Career Network

Affiliations

  • Online ISSN 1467-9752
  • Print ISSN 0309-8249
  • Copyright © 2024 Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain
  • About Oxford Academic
  • Publish journals with us
  • University press partners
  • What we publish
  • New features  
  • Open access
  • Institutional account management
  • Rights and permissions
  • Get help with access
  • Accessibility
  • Advertising
  • Media enquiries
  • Oxford University Press
  • Oxford Languages
  • University of Oxford

Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University's objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide

  • Copyright © 2024 Oxford University Press
  • Cookie settings
  • Cookie policy
  • Privacy policy
  • Legal notice

This Feature Is Available To Subscribers Only

Sign In or Create an Account

This PDF is available to Subscribers Only

For full access to this pdf, sign in to an existing account, or purchase an annual subscription.

Duke University Press Logo

  • Advertisers
  • Agents and Vendors
  • Book Authors and Editors
  • Booksellers / Media / Review Copies
  • Librarians and Consortia
  • Journal Authors and Editors
  • Licensing and Subsidiary Rights
  • Mathematics Authors and Editors
  • Prospective Journals
  • Scholarly Publishing Collective
  • Explore Subjects
  • Authors and Editors
  • Society Members and Officers
  • Prospective Societies

Open Access

  • Job Opportunities

Debating Moral Education

Rethinking the role of the modern university.

Debating Moral Education

Editor(s): Elizabeth Kiss , J. Peter Euben

Contributor(s): Noah Pickus , Elizabeth Kiss , Julie A. Reuben , Stanley Fish , Stanley Hauerwas , Elizabeth Spelman , Wilson Carey McWilliams , Lawrence Blum , James Bernard Murphy , Patchen Markell , George Shulman , Romand Coles , David . Hoekema , J. Donald Moon , Ruth W. Grant , Michael Gillespie , J. Peter Euben , Susan McWilliams

Subjects Pedagogy and Higher Education , Religious Studies , Politics > Political Theory

“ Debating Moral Education is a provocative and productive collection, which can positively impact the teaching and practice of moral education in the academy. While the authors are not of one voice on the subject, their thorough and passionate responses evoke deeper thought about the practice of moral education. Their lively conversation invites the participation of a wide audience of faculty, administrators, student affairs professionals, as well as the larger community. Many of these essays can also provide students with an opening to think about their own education and the role of the university.” — Matthew Maruggi, Teaching Theology and Religion

“ Debating Moral Education makes an indispensable contribution to moral education’s expanding bibliography.” — Jerry Pattengale, Books & Culture

“[An] engaging collection of essays by prominent scholars from religious, philosophical, and political backgrounds who debate the role of morality and ethics in the university. . . . Readers who begin this book can easily imagine themselves caught up in the unfolding, urgent, but friendly controversy of scholarly opinions regarding moral education.” — Lois Calian Trautvetter, Review of Higher Education

“Elizabeth Kiss and Peter Euben's Debating Moral Education brings together an impressive group of philosophers, political scientists and, in the case of Stanley Hauerwas, a theologian to discuss these matters. . . . The strength of the volume lies in the editors' determination to give voice to a range of different views and leave readers (free) to pick their own way through.” — J. Mark Halstead, Times Higher Education

“This is an excellent book, offering a great deal for many educators globally. It is timely, articulate and thought-provoking.” — Joseph Zajda, International Review of Education

“Those interested in its topic would be well advised to read this book. . . .The contributors draw from an impressive variety of fields of inquiry to support their positions on both sides of the question. The cumulative effect is a nuanced overview of many considerations important to the debate, illuminated by thinkers as diverse as Socrates, Plato, Dewey, Marx, Bloch,Nietzsche, Nussbaum, Arendt and Foucault.” — Daniel Vokey, Journal of Moral Education

“Recently colleges and universities that had for many years distanced themselves from their students’ growth as moral agents have begun taking this aspect of higher education very seriously. In this book they will find the issues laid out with admirable clarity and the fresh ideas and approaches they need to do the work well.” — W. Robert Connor, Professor of Classics, Emeritus, Princeton University

“Some of the best scholars in the field engage in the contemporary debate over the nature and scope of moral education, especially in American universities. Anyone wishing to trace this complex but fascinating debate would do well to read Debating Moral Education .” — Terence Ball, author of Reappraising Political Theory

“This excellent collection of essays provides a timely and thoughtful account of the perils and prospects of moral education in our time. The contributors are prominent moral philosophers, political theorists, and civic educators whose different perspectives—some enthusiastic, others wary—make for a lively and reflective volume. The issues raised in this important book will interest and challenge students and educators in a context defined by related debates over academic freedom, intelligent design, and the ever-present culture wars.” — James Farr, University of Minnesota

  • Buy the e-book: Amazon Kindle Apple iBooks Barnes & Noble nook Google Play Kobo
  • Author/Editor Bios
  • Table of Contents
  • Additional Information

Elizabeth Kiss is President of Agnes Scott College. J. Peter Euben is Professor of Political Science, Research Professor of Classical Studies, and Kenan Distinguished Faculty Fellow in Ethics at Duke University. He is the author of Platonic Noise , Corrupting Youth , and The Tragedy of Political Theory , and an editor of Athenian Political Thought and the Reconstruction of American Democracy .

If you are requesting permission to photocopy material for classroom use, please contact the Copyright Clearance Center at copyright.com;

If the Copyright Clearance Center cannot grant permission, you may request permission from our Copyrights & Permissions Manager (use Contact Information listed below).

If you are requesting permission to reprint DUP material (journal or book selection) in another book or in any other format, contact our Copyrights & Permissions Manager (use Contact Information listed below).

Many images/art used in material copyrighted by Duke University Press are controlled, not by the Press, but by the owner of the image. Please check the credit line adjacent to the illustration, as well as the front and back matter of the book for a list of credits. You must obtain permission directly from the owner of the image. Occasionally, Duke University Press controls the rights to maps or other drawings. Please direct permission requests for these images to [email protected] . For book covers to accompany reviews, please contact the publicity department .

If you're interested in a Duke University Press book for subsidiary rights/translations, please contact [email protected] . Include the book title/author, rights sought, and estimated print run.

Instructions for requesting an electronic text on behalf of a student with disabilities are available here .

Email: [email protected] Email contact for coursepacks: [email protected] Fax: 919-688-4574 Mail: Duke University Press Rights and Permissions 905 W. Main Street Suite 18B Durham, NC 27701

1. Author's name. If book has an editor that is different from the article author, include editor's name also. 2. Title of the journal article or book chapter and title of journal or title of book 3. Page numbers (if excerpting, provide specifics) For coursepacks, please also note: The number of copies requested, the school and professor requesting For reprints and subsidiary rights, please also note: Your volume title, publication date, publisher, print run, page count, rights sought

This book is subject to the standard Duke University Press rights and permissions.

  • read Michael Allen Gillespie's essay on the NCAA Men's Basketball championship
  • David Brooks cites Michael Allen Gillespie in his essay "The Sporting Mind" in the February 4, 2010 issue of The New York Times
  • Bk Cover Image Full
  • Also Viewed
  • Also Purchased

On Being Included

moral education essay questions

The Problem with Work

moral education essay questions

Vibrant Matter

moral education essay questions

The American Colonial State in the Philippines

moral education essay questions

Necropolitics

moral education essay questions

Conspiracy/Theory

moral education essay questions

On Decoloniality

moral education essay questions

Israel/Palestine and the Queer International

moral education essay questions

Bad Education

Bad Education

Making the World Global

Making the World Global

Pikachu's Global Adventure

Pikachu's Global Adventure

Poor Queer Studies

Poor Queer Studies

99 Moral Development Essay Topic Ideas & Examples

🏆 best moral development topic ideas & essay examples, 📌 simple & easy moral development essay titles, 👍 good essay topics on moral development, ❓ questions about moral development.

  • Kohlberg’s Moral Development Concept This is continuous because, in every stage of the moral development, the moral reasoning changes to become increasingly complex over the years.
  • Aggression Development: Piaget’s Moral Development Theory It is the first stage of moral development in which a child views the rules of authority figures as revered and unchangeable. We will write a custom essay specifically for you by our professional experts 808 writers online Learn More
  • School Bullying and Moral Development The middle childhood is marked by the development of basic literacy skills and understanding of other people’s behavior that would be crucial in creating effective later social cognitions. Therefore, addressing bullying in schools requires strategies […]
  • Kohlberg’s Stages of Moral Development in Justice System Burglars, whose predominant level of morality is conventional, tend to consider the opinion of the society on their actions. Kohlberg’s stages of moral development help to identify the problems and find solutions to them.
  • Pulp Fiction: Moral Development of American Life and Interests Quentin Tarantino introduces his Pulp Fiction by means of several scenes which have a certain sequence: proper enlightenment, strong and certain camera movements and shots, focus on some details and complete ignorance of the others, […]
  • Moral Development in Early Childhood The only point to be poorly addressed in this discussion is the options for assessing values in young children and the worth of this task.
  • The Moral Development of Children Child development Rev 2000; 71: 1033 1048.’ moral development/moral reasoning which is an important aspect of cognitive development of children has been studied very thoroughly with evidence-based explanations from the work of many psychologists based […]
  • Moral Development and Bullying in Children The understanding of moral development following the theories of Kohlberg and Gilligan can provide useful solutions to eliminating bullying in American schools.
  • Kohlberg’s Theory of Moral Development Dilemma According to Kohlberg, justice is the driver of the process of moral development. Therefore, the early Christians should have continued to practice Christianity regardless of the persecution.
  • Moral Development: Emotion and Moral Behavior More moral emotion is guilt as compared to shame because those who are shamed are relatively unlikely to rectify as compared to the guilty people.
  • Adolescent Moral Development in the United States Adolescents who are in this stage begin to acknowledge and understand the beliefs embraced in their societies. The absence of a moral compass can make it hard for adolescents in this country to realize their […]
  • Moral Development Theory Review by Kohlberg and Hersh Overall, the main strength of this article is that the authors present a comprehensive overview of theories that can throw light on the moral development of a person.
  • Moral Development and Aggression The reason is that children conclude about the acceptability of aggressive or violent behaviors with reference to what they see and hear in their family and community.
  • Moral Development: Kohlberg’s Dilemmas Another characteristic of this stage of moral speculation is that the speculators mostly view the dilemma through the lens of consequences it might result in and engage them in a direct or indirect manner.
  • Chinese Foundations for Moral Education and Character Development In Chinese Foundations for Moral Education and Character Development, Vincent Shen and his team make a wonderful attempt to describe how rich and captivating Chinese cultural heritage may be, how considerable knowledge for this country […]
  • Cognitive, Psychosocial, Psychosexual and Moral Development This, he goes ahead to explain that it is at this very stage that children learn to be self sufficient in terms of taking themselves to the bathroom, feeding and even walking.
  • Moral Development and Ethical Concepts The two concepts are important in the promotion of ethical culture within the organizations, the organizations’ performance and the much needed moral and financial support from the organization’s stakeholders and the public in general.
  • Empathy and Moral Development For a manager to have empathy, he/she has to be able to interact freely with the employees, and spend time with them at their work places. This makes the employees to know that what they […]
  • Cognitive or Moral Development This is the second of the four Piagetian stages of development and the children begin to make use of words, pictures and diagrams to represent their sentiments.
  • Moral Intelligence Development In the course of his day-to-day banking activities, I realized that the general manager used to work in line with the banking rules and regulations to the letter.
  • An Evaluation of Kohlberg’s Theory of Moral Development and How It Could Be Applied to Grade School It is the purpose of this essay to summarize Kohlberg’s theory, and thereafter analyze how the theory can be applied to grade a school.
  • Moral Development and Its Relation to Psychology These stages reveal the individual’s moral orientation expanding his/her experiences and perceptions of the world with regard to the cognitive development of a person admitting this expansion. The views of Piaget and Kohlberg differ in […]
  • The Impact Of Television On The Moral Development
  • Influences in Moral Development
  • The Influence of Parenting in the Moral Development of a Child
  • The Effect of Cognitive Moral Development on Honesty in Managerial Reporting
  • Huckleberry Finn Moral Development & Changes
  • Responsibility For Moral Development In Children
  • Morality and Responsibility – Moral Development in Mary Shelley’s Frankenstein
  • Moral Development And Gender Care Theories
  • Jean Piaget and Lawrence Kohlberg on Moral Development
  • Kaylee Georgeoff’s Moral Development According To Lawrence Kohlberg
  • The Criticisms Of Kohlberg’s Moral Development Stages
  • The Ethics Of The Organization ‘s Moral Development
  • Lawrence Kohlbergs Stages Of Moral Development
  • Personal, Psychosocial, And Moral Development Theories
  • Moral Development and Importance of Moral Reasoning
  • Integrating Care and Justice: Moral Development
  • Moral Development in Youth Sport
  • Kohlberg’s Theory on Moral Development: New Field of Study in Western Science
  • The Definition of Ethics and the Foundation of Moral Development
  • Kohleberg´s Philosophy of Moral Development
  • Stealing and Moral Reasoning: Kohlberg’s Stages of Moral Development
  • Plagiarism and Moral Development
  • Kohlberg and Moral Development Between the Ages of One and Six
  • Kohlberg’s 6 Stages of Cognitive Moral Development and Model Suggestions
  • Moral Development and Narcissism of Private and Public University Business Students
  • The Effect of the Transcendental Meditation TM Technique on Moral Development
  • Psychology Stages of Moral Development
  • The Link Between Friendship and Moral Development
  • Moral Development And Gender Related Reasoning Styles
  • Moral Development in the Adventures of Huckleberry Fin by Mark Twain
  • Moral Development : The Way Someone Thinks, Feels, And Behaves
  • The Effect of Nuclear and Joint Family Systems on the Moral Development: A Gender Based Analysis
  • Moral Development and Dilemmas of Huck in The Adventures of Huckleberry Finn by Mark Twain
  • Teaching Moral Development To School Children In The Caribbean
  • History and Moral Development of Mental Health Treatment and Involuntary Commitment
  • Incorporating Kohlberg’s Stages of Moral Development into the Justice System
  • Moral Development Theory in Boys and Girls: Kohlberg and Gilligan
  • The Different Levels in Moral Development
  • Moral Development Of Six-Year-Old Children
  • Portrait of Erik Erikson’s Developmental Theory and Kohlberg’s Model of Moral Development
  • Moral Development Of Jem And Scout In To Kill A Mockingbird
  • Moral Development and Aggression in Children
  • The Idea Of Moral Development In The Novel Adventures of Huckleberry Finn By Mark Twain
  • The Influence of Media Technology on the Moral Development and Self-Concept of Youth
  • The Character of Tituba in Lawrence Kohlberg’s Different Stages of Moral Development
  • Multiple Intelligences, Metacognition And Moral Development
  • Moral Development : The Foundation Of Ethical Behavior
  • Can Moral Development Lead To Upward Influence Behavior?
  • What Are the Five Stages of Moral Development?
  • What Is an Example of Moral Development?
  • What Is Moral Development, and Why Is It Important?
  • What Are the Three Levels of Moral Development?
  • What Are the Six Stages of Kohlberg’s Theory of Moral Development?
  • What Is Moral Development in a Child?
  • What Is Moral Development, According to Kohlberg?
  • How Many Levels of Moral Development Are There?
  • Why Is Moral Development Significant in Early Childhood?
  • What Factors Play Into Moral Development?
  • What Is Moral Development in Adolescence?
  • What Are the Characteristics of Moral Development?
  • Why Is Kohlberg’s Theory of Moral Development Critical?
  • What Characteristics Are Essential for Healthy Moral Development?
  • How Do Parents Affect a Child’s Moral Development?
  • What Is the Most Important Influence on a Child’s Moral Development?
  • What Is the Role of the Teacher in Moral Development?
  • Why Is Moral Development Significant?
  • What Is Meant by Moral Development?
  • Why Is Research on Moral Development Necessary?
  • What Is the Study of Moral Development?
  • What Factors Affect Moral Development?
  • Which of the Following Researchers Studied Moral Development?
  • How Did Kohlberg Research Moral Development?
  • What Is Carol Gilligan’s Theory of Moral Development?
  • How Did Piaget Study Moral Development?
  • What Was Gilligan’s Main Criticism of Kohlberg’s Theory of Moral Development?
  • What Is the Difference Between Kohlberg’s Theory of Moral Development and Gilligan’s Theory of Moral Evolution and Gender?
  • Why Do Different Scholars Criticize Kohlberg’s Theory of Moral Development?
  • Chicago (A-D)
  • Chicago (N-B)

IvyPanda. (2023, September 26). 99 Moral Development Essay Topic Ideas & Examples. https://ivypanda.com/essays/topic/moral-development-essay-topics/

"99 Moral Development Essay Topic Ideas & Examples." IvyPanda , 26 Sept. 2023, ivypanda.com/essays/topic/moral-development-essay-topics/.

IvyPanda . (2023) '99 Moral Development Essay Topic Ideas & Examples'. 26 September.

IvyPanda . 2023. "99 Moral Development Essay Topic Ideas & Examples." September 26, 2023. https://ivypanda.com/essays/topic/moral-development-essay-topics/.

1. IvyPanda . "99 Moral Development Essay Topic Ideas & Examples." September 26, 2023. https://ivypanda.com/essays/topic/moral-development-essay-topics/.

Bibliography

IvyPanda . "99 Moral Development Essay Topic Ideas & Examples." September 26, 2023. https://ivypanda.com/essays/topic/moral-development-essay-topics/.

  • Developmental Psychology Essay Ideas
  • Morality Research Ideas
  • Cognitive Development Essay Ideas
  • Social Responsibility Topics
  • Emotional Development Questions
  • Human Development Research Ideas
  • Ethnicity Research Topics
  • Organization Development Research Ideas
  • Personality Development Ideas
  • Professional Development Research Ideas
  • Respect Essay Topics
  • Ethics Ideas
  • Lifespan Development Essay Titles
  • Social Development Essay Topics
  • Ethical Dilemma Titles

Advertisement

Advertisement

Moral Disagreement and Moral Education: What’s the Problem?

  • Open access
  • Published: 05 June 2023
  • Volume 27 , pages 5–24, ( 2024 )

Cite this article

You have full access to this open access article

  • Dominik Balg   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0003-2078-9312 1  

1413 Accesses

Explore all metrics

Although initially plausible, the view that moral education should aim at the transmission of moral knowledge has been subject to severe criticism. In this context, one particularly prominent line of argumentation rests on the empirical observation that moral questions are subject to widespread and robust disagreement. In this paper, I would like to discuss the implications of moral disagreement for the goals of moral education in more detail. I will start by laying out the empirical and philosophical assumptions behind the idea that widespread and robust moral disagreement undermines the prospects of transmitting moral knowledge in educational settings. Having thus provided a specific interpretation of the epistemic dynamics behind this so-called ‘challenge of disagreement’, I will proceed by discussing its didactical implications. More specifically, I will defend two claims: first, I will argue that the challenge of disagreement is not an effective challenge, because it undermines the possibility of knowledge transfer only with respect to a limited set of moral propositions. Second, I will argue that the challenge of disagreement is not a specific challenge, because the epistemically destructive effects of moral disagreement also pose a challenge for other prominent accounts of moral education that were originally proposed as promising alternatives to knowledge transmission accounts. If convincing, my arguments show that knowledge transmission accounts of moral education are in a much better position than is usually expected to incorporate the fact that moral questions are notoriously controversial.

Similar content being viewed by others

moral education essay questions

Evolution and Revolution in Artificial Intelligence in Education

Ido Roll & Ruth Wylie

moral education essay questions

Ethics of AI in Education: Towards a Community-Wide Framework

Wayne Holmes, Kaska Porayska-Pomsta, … Kenneth R. Koedinger

Discourses of artificial intelligence in higher education: a critical literature review

Margaret Bearman, Juliana Ryan & Rola Ajjawi

Avoid common mistakes on your manuscript.

1 Introduction

What are the goals of moral education? One possible answer to this question is the following: moral education is simply education with respect to a specific topic. Accordingly, the goals of moral education are simply general educational goals that are applied to this specific topic . Viewed from this perspective, there is nothing special about moral education. For example, let’s assume that the transmission of knowledge is one important general goal of education. Given this, we could simply apply this goal to a variety of specific educational domains. One important goal of science education would be the transmission of scientific knowledge. One important goal of history education would be the transmission of historical knowledge. And one important goal of moral education would be the transmission of moral knowledge. Footnote 1

Although initially intuitive, many if not most authors within the didactics of philosophy and the philosophy of education will likely reject the above idea. One main reason for this reluctance to regard the transmission of moral knowledge as an important goal of moral education is the worry that – given widespread philosophical disagreement about moral questions – such transmission is simply impossible: if all or most moral questions are subject to widespread and robust disagreement, there won’t be much transferable moral knowledge to begin with, so that any attempt to directly transmit specific moral beliefs would simply amount to indoctrination (Hand 2018 , 1).

In this paper, I would like to discuss this challenge of disagreement in more detail. More specifically, I will defend two claims. First, I will argue that the challenge of disagreement is not an effective challenge, because it undermines the possibility of knowledge transfer only with respect to a limited set of moral propositions. Second, I will argue that the challenge of disagreement is not a specific challenge for knowledge transmission accounts of moral education, because the epistemically destructive effects of moral disagreement also pose a challenge for other prominent accounts of moral education. I will proceed as follows. In Section  2 , I will start by laying out the empirical and philosophical assumptions behind the challenge of disagreement, conceived as a specific epistemic challenge for moral knowledge transmission, in more detail. Having thus provided a specific interpretation of the epistemic dynamics behind the challenge of disagreement, I will proceed by discussing its didactical implications in more detail. In Section  3 , I will critically discuss the efficacy of the challenge of disagreement, arguing that it doesn’t undermine the possibility of moral knowledge transmission in general, but only with respect to specific first-order moral propositions that are sufficiently controversial among professional ethicists. In Section  4 , I will discuss the accuracy of the challenge of disagreement, arguing that it also undermines other dimensions of moral education that were originally proposed as promising alternatives to moral knowledge transmission, such as teaching moral reasoning skills or enabling students to participate in moral discourse. Section 5  will sum up the main results.

If convincing, my arguments show that knowledge transmission accounts of moral education are not just better than widely assumed, but actually do better than their main competitors in dealing with the educational implications of moral disagreement. However, I want to stay explicitly neutral on the question of whether knowledge transmission accounts are superior overall to alternative accounts of moral education – or whether they are even feasible at all. Besides the problem of disagreement, there are a number of further challenges that knowledge transmission accounts of moral education must face. Most importantly, these accounts seem to rest on a number of controversial epistemological assumptions – e.g. assumptions about the existence of moral experts or the possibility of moral testimony. While I am personally optimistic that many of the various objections lurking in this context can be successfully met, any detailed discussion of them would clearly exceed the scope of this paper. What’s more, even if we assume that knowledge transmission accounts of moral education are epistemically defensible, there will still be political and pedagogical challenges to the idea that moral knowledge should be directly transmitted in educational contexts (for an overview, see e.g. Giesinger 2021 ). Accordingly, all I want to argue for in the following is the comparatively narrow claim that the specific phenomenon of moral disagreement is not so much a problem for knowledge transmission accounts as it is for competing accounts of moral education. While clearly being comparatively narrow, this claim still has bite: in fact, the challenge of disagreement is often seen as one of the most pressing problems for moral education in the relevant literature (Hand 2018 , p. 1). Given that, a satisfactory solution of this specific challenge would already lead to a significant shift in the dialectical landscape.

Before I proceed, however, and in order to avoid misunderstandings, I would like to make an important conceptual clarification. Especially for experienced educators, the idea that „knowledge transmission “ should be a goal of any kind of education might already raise some concerns. To better understand this idea, it is helpful to distinguish between an epistemological, a psychological and a didactical reading of “knowledge transmission”. According to the epistemological reading, this notion only refers to a specific epistemic relation between the input beliefs and the output beliefs of educational transfer processes. According to the psychological reading, the transmission of knowledge also includes the transmission of psychological features that concern the cognitive embeddedness of beliefs. According to the didactical reading, “transmission of knowledge “ refers to top-down educational settings where instructors simply impart knowledge to their students instead of enabling them to acquire the relevant insights on their own. While the educational importance of knowledge transmission in the epistemological sense has been widely acknowledged (see e.g. Goldman 2006 , p.11)—in fact, it is epistemologically uncontroversial that most of what we know we only know on the basis of other people’s knowledge (see e.g. Goldberg 2010 )—knowledge transmission in the psychological and didactical sense is usually judged to be pedagogically illegitimate or even impossible. Footnote 2 In this paper, whenever I speak of „knowledge transmission “, I speak of knowledge transmission in the epistemological sense. Aiming at the transmission of knowledge in this sense in educational contexts is both compatible with psychological findings to the effect that the acquisition of knowledge is rather a result of individual construction than of passive perception and with the didactical demand that students should acquire insights on their own (Hand 2018 , 38).

2 The Epistemic Dynamics behind the Challenge of Disagreement

At first glance, the idea that the pervasiveness of moral disagreement directly speaks against the possibility of educational transfers of moral knowledge seems pretty straightforward. However, upon closer inspection, it is at least not obvious why and how the controversiality of moral issues is supposed to undermine educational transfer processes. After all, one might argue, people disagree about almost everything – and still, at least in domains like mathematics, science, history or geography, educational transfer of substantive, domain-specific insights seems to be perfectly legitimate. So why should the mere fact that moral questions are notoriously controversial pose a specific problem for the educational transmission of moral knowledge?

To answer this question, I would like to provide a deeper analysis of the challenge of disagreement in this section. In order to get a better grasp of the philosophical details behind this challenge, it is helpful to cite one of its proponents in a little more detail. So, to begin with, consider the following passage from Kirsten Meyer (Meyer 2011 , p. 229 f., my translation):

Let‘s suppose that there are in fact specific moral principles whose correctness we are able to grasp and upon which we can act. Even against the background of this assumption, there remains an important problem for moral education. After all, it is still not clear at all which moral principles are correct – and accordingly, which principles should be taught in educational settings. One simple reason why moral education can‘t be aimed at the transmission of moral principles is that such principles are controversial within academic philosophy. If moral education was about transferring knowledge of correct moral principles, one would first need to know which exact principles these should be. […] Which principles should be taught in philosophy classes in order to enable students to act morally? Should we advocate for a kantian or a utilitarian position? Do we have to wait for the underlying philosophical disputes to be settled before we can answer this question? […] When we try to identify the proper goals of moral education […], we encounter […] several open questions. A satisfying answer to these questions would require a settlement of century-old philosophical disputes. And such a settlement is not to be expected.

Against the background of this passage, the dialectical profile of the challenge of disagreement already becomes clearer. Most importantly, it becomes clear that the challenge of disagreement is a specific objection against knowledge transmission accounts of moral education that already rests on a number of specific assumptions: first of all, the basic idea behind this challenge is not that it is in principle impossible to transfer moral knowledge in educational settings – e.g. because there aren ‘t any moral principles, or because such principles aren’t truth-apt. Rather, the idea is that in light of widespread moral disagreement, it isn ‘t clear which moral principles should be transferred in educational settings. In this way, the challenge of disagreement already presupposes the possibility of moral knowledge. And in fact, this shouldn’t come as a surprise: for instance, let ‘s suppose that a fundamentally pessimistic view on the possibility of moral knowledge –e.g. moral nihilism or moral non-cognitivism—was correct. In such a case, it seems that whether moral questions are in fact controversial or not would be completely irrelevant to the possibility of moral knowledge transfer, because even if everyone agreed on the same moral verdicts, we still wouldn ‘t be in a position to transfer any moral knowledge in educational settings. The challenge of disagreement is supposed to show that crucial features of moral knowledge transfers are effectively undermined by the fact that moral questions are notoriously controversial. But if there is nothing to be undermined in the first place, this idea seems like a nonstarter.

Furthermore, the challenge of disagreement explicitly presupposes that moral questions are controversial among professional philosophers and that it is exactly this kind of disagreement that undermines the possibility of moral knowledge transfer. In fact, it is important to note that in the above passage, Meyer isn’t just talking about any old moral disagreement, but rather specifically refers to moral disagreements within academic philosophy , e.g. between kantians and utilitarians. But what’s so special about moral disagreements between academic philosophers? The idea seems to be here that – just as educational knowledge transfer in other domains – educational transfer of moral knowledge should be informed by the relevant experts. However, given that even the experts disagree about moral questions, we are in no position to decide which moral principles should be taught in educational settings. In what follows, I would like to discuss these assumptions behind the challenge of disagreement in a little more detail in order to provide a more fine-grained understanding of the prima facie plausible idea that widespread moral disagreement poses a fundamental problem for educational transfer of moral knowledge.

Let ‘s start with the assumption that it is in principle possible to acquire moral knowledge. As we have seen, this assumption is implicitly presupposed by the challenge of disagreement, because if it was impossible to acquire any moral knowledge in the first place, it would be completely irrelevant whether moral questions are in fact controversial or not. Given how extensively pessimistic views on the possibility of moral knowledge have been discussed in the philosophical literature, this already seems like a substantive and potentially problematic metaethical commitment. However, there are several things to be said to soften the worry that the challenge of disagreement can simply be rejected by appealing to some form of metaethical pessimism. First of all, the assumption that we are in principle in a position to acquire moral knowledge doesn ‘t just underlie the challenge of disagreement, but also much of our everyday moral practice: at least from a pretheoretical perspective, it seems overwhelmingly plausible that we can and actually do have a lot of moral knowledge. For example, most people would agree that I know that torturing puppies out of boredom is morally wrong, or that I ‘m not morally obliged to compliment random strangers on their outfits. Given this, the fact that the challenge of disagreement questions the legitimacy of moral knowledge transfer on the basis of critical considerations concerning the scope —and not the mere possibility – of moral knowledge seems to be a strength and not a weakness.

Furthermore, and more importantly, the assumption that it is in principle possible to acquire moral knowledge is obviously already presupposed by the very target of the challenge of disagreement – i.e. by knowledge transmission accounts of moral education. Proponents of these accounts cannot defend themselves against the challenge of disagreement on the basis of pessimistic views on the possibility of moral knowledge without undermining their own position. Given this, any critique of the challenge of disagreement that points to the optimistic presuppositions that this challenge implies with respect to the possibility of moral knowledge seems to be at least dialectically ineffective.

Notably, the same is true with respect to the second assumption behind the challenge of disagreement that has been identified above – the assumption that moral questions are controversial among professional philosophers and that it is exactly this kind of disagreement that undermines the possibility of moral knowledge transfer. One rather obvious problem with this assumption is that it seems to presuppose that academic philosophers enjoy some kind of moral expertise and are thus in a privileged position to inform educational transfer processes. This presupposition will probably strike many people as hopelessly elitist (Driver 2006 ) – but again, it is plausibly already presupposed by knowledge transmission accounts of moral education. Footnote 3 For as already illustrated at the outset of this paper, the very idea behind these accounts seems to be that there is nothing special about moral education: just as in other domains, educational processes in the moral domain should be aimed at the transmission of domain-specific knowledge that is provided by the relevant academic community. Given this, proponents of these accounts cannot defend themselves against the challenge of disagreement by rejecting its presuppositions concerning the possibility of moral expertise without undermining their own position.

So let‘s suppose that professional philosophers can plausibly be considered as moral experts. Is it true that moral questions are controversial among professional philosophers? And how exactly are these disagreements supposed to undermine the possibility of educational knowledge transfer? The first of these questions is clearly an empirical one. However, it is surprisingly hard to answer. One obvious difficulty is to identify the relevant group of people in the first place – what does it even mean to be a philosopher? And is every philosopher an expert on any philosophical question? Footnote 4 Furthermore, many widespread views on the amount of controversy within academic philosophy will likely be distorted by naive misconceptions and prejudices which portray philosophy as a messy and hopelessly unoriented endeavor.

Despite all these difficulties and biases, there has been one notable attempt to get a clearer picture of the amount and distribution of disagreement among professional philosophers that has received a lot of attention within the philosophical community. In their much-discussed PhilPapers Surveys, David Chalmers and David Bourget regularly survey professional philosophers in order to help uncover their views on key philosophical questions. The results of this project allow for a more justified estimation of the degree of moral disagreement among experts. For example, considering only the answers of respondents who are regular faculty members in BA-granting philosophy departments, and who named “normative ethics” as their area of specialization, the 2020 PhilPapers Survey revealed a fundamental disagreement about which ethical theory is correct (for the following numbers, see Bourget and Chalmers 2021 ). While 27.27% accept or lean toward deontology, 20.45% accept or lean toward consequentialism. 17.42% accept or lean toward virtue ethics and 0.76% are agnostic or undecided. In fact, it looks like the degree of controversy has even increased over the last few years. For, in the preceding PhilPapers Survey of 2009, 35.25% accepted or leaned toward deontology, 23.02% accepted or leaned toward consequentialism, and 12.23% accepted or leaned toward virtue ethics (Bourget and Chalmers 2014 ). While it is also important to keep in mind that (i) conflicting ethical theories don ‘t necessarily yield conflicting verdicts with respect to all or even most concrete moral questions and (ii) proponents of the same ethical theory regularly end up with conflicting applications of this theory, these numbers clearly justify the assumption that a lot of concrete moral issues will be highly controversial among the relevant experts.

Why is such a high degree of controversy among experts a serious problem for moral knowledge transmission? In what follows, I would like to provide a specific interpretation of the epistemic dynamics behind the idea that widespread expert disagreement undermines the possibility of educational knowledge transfer. This interpretation is directly informed by the recent debate about the epistemic implications of disagreement within social epistemology. One important insight from this debate is that the epistemic implications of a situation of disagreement crucially depend on the respective levels of competence of the disagreeing parties (see e.g. Kelly 2005 , p. 168). In this context, one specific constellation of cases that have received a lot of attention within the epistemological literature are disagreement situations where the disagreeing parties are epistemic peers , which means that the disagreeing parties have access to the same (or equally good) evidence and are equally competent in assessing this evidence (Christensen 2009 , pp. 756–757). Footnote 5 One reason why such cases have received so much attention within the epistemological literature is that they apparently have profound epistemic implications. More specifically, peer disagreements seem to make it epistemically irrational to hold on to one’s beliefs. For, whenever a person finds herself in disagreement with someone she considers her epistemic peer, she is rationally required to revise her original position. To illustrate this point, many authors refer to the so-called Restaurant Case which was originally developed by Christensen ( 2007 ). The case goes as follows (ibid., p. 193):

Suppose that five of us go out to dinner. It’s time to pay the check, so the question we’re interested in is how much we each owe. We can all see the bill total clearly, we all agree to give a 20% tip, and we further agree to split the whole cost evenly […]. I do the math in my head and become highly confident that our shares are $43 each. Meanwhile, my friend does the math in her head and becomes highly confident that our shares are $45 each. How should I react, upon learning of her belief? […] Let us suppose that my friend and I have a long history of eating out together and dividing the check in our heads, and that we’ve been equally successful in our arithmetic efforts: the vast majority of times, we agree; but when we disagree, she’s right as often as I am. So for the sort of epistemic endeavor under consideration, we are clearly peers. Suppose further that there is no special reason to think one of us particularly dull or sharp this evening—neither is especially tired or energetic, and neither has had significantly more wine or coffee.

In this case, many authors agree that the protagonist of the case is rationally required to give up her belief that the share is $43 each. Although there is some considerable disagreement about the relevant epistemic mechanics behind the rationally required response in such a case, and its exact doxastic nature, there is wide agreement that the described situation requires a state of substantive uncertainty (for a discussion, see e.g. Christensen 2007 ; Grundmann 2019 ; Kelly 2011 ). While this verdict and its generalization over all cases of peer disagreement can – and actually has been (see e.g. Kelly 2005 , 2011 ) – disputed, I will assume a conciliationist view in what follows, according to which situations of recognized peer disagreement undermine the epistemic status of the conflicting beliefs. Footnote 6 If we assume a conciliationist view on the significance of disagreement and combine this view with the above assumption about the degree of controversy among professional ethicists, it is easy to see how moral disagreements directly lead to a problem for the possibility of moral knowledge transfer. In situations where the relevant experts agree, disagreement with laypeople doesn’t pose a problem for such transfers, because it doesn’t undermine the experts’ knowledge, which is the ultimate source of the transfer processes. However, this is not the case in situations where the relevant experts disagree with each other . Footnote 7 For, if even the experts are (or should be) in a state of substantive uncertainty about the questions at issue, they are in no position to inform educational transfer processes. Footnote 8

I take the epistemic dynamics that has been delineated above to be the most plausible interpretation of the assumption that widespread expert disagreement undermines the possibility of moral knowledge transfer in educational settings. This interpretation doesn’t only neatly explain how the controversiality of moral questions might undermine the possibility of such knowledge transfers, but also sheds some light on the significance of agreement for moral education. Given the epistemic dynamics analyzed above, it gets clear that the absence of (sufficiently robust) disagreement among moral experts is a necessary condition for moral knowledge transfer. However, that doesn’t necessarily mean that (sufficiently robust) agreement among moral experts is necessary for knowledge transfer. To see this, we just have to consider situations in which widespread agreement among experts is absent because only a very small fraction of the expert community has formed any beliefs on a given question, because this question hasn’t even been considered by most of their colleagues. If we assume that the beliefs of these few experts constitute knowledge, this status will in no way be undermined by the mere fact that other experts don’t agree. Furthermore, moral agreement is also not sufficient for moral knowledge transfer to be legitimate or even possible. For example, if we have good reasons to believe that a specific group of experts is fundamentally corrupt or misguided, the mere fact that they agree with each other should be of no relevance. In this way, the above interpretation doesn’t just help to better understand the challenge of disagreement, but also to locate its dialectical profile more accurately.

As we have seen in this section, the challenge of disagreement is a specific challenge for knowledge transmission accounts of moral education that rests on a number of specific empirical and philosophical assumptions. Some of these assumptions are more controversial than others, and some also have to be presupposed by proponents of knowledge transmission accounts. In what follows, I would not like to discuss these assumptions in more detail. Instead, I will simply accept them in order to make the challenge of disagreement as strong as possible. For as we will see, even if we accept all the assumptions that underlie the challenge of disagreement, it will still fail to pose a devastating problem for knowledge transmission accounts of moral education.

3 The Efficacy of the Challenge of Disagreement

In the last section, we saw why moral disagreement among professional ethicists poses a fundamental challenge to the possibility of moral knowledge transfer. That is, if professional ethicists are rationally required to adopt a stance of uncertainty with respect to moral questions, then they are in no position to present their moral views as knowledge to laypeople. In this section, I would like to critically discuss the efficacy of this challenge in more detail. Obviously, moral disagreement among professional ethicists has profound implications for the prospects of moral knowledge transfer. Yet, at the same time, it seems that it doesn’t undermine all transfer of moral knowledge, but only with respect to certain propositions . As we saw in the last section, the challenge of disagreement as it stands ultimately rests on the observation that professional ethicists disagree about which moral theory is correct (Meyer 2011 , pp. 229–230). Given this, professional ethicists will also disagree about any first-order moral question to which their competing moral theories imply conflicting answers, which in turn will undermine any possibility of knowledge transfer with respect to these questions. However, as I will argue in this section, there will also be a lot of moral questions which are subject to substantive agreement – and with respect to these questions, the challenge of disagreement remains ineffective.

At first glance, to someone who is familiar with the relevant literature, it might seem that this is something that has already been done. For example, in his paper ‚Towards a Theory of Moral Education ‘, Michael Hand, a prominent proponent of knowledge transmission accounts of moral education, writes (Hand 2014 , p. 528):

[…] Disagreement about the justificatory status of many moral standards […] looks set to be a salient feature of our moral landscape for the foreseeable future. But it would [be] premature to infer from this state of affairs that robustly justified moral standards are unavailable. From the fact that some moral standards have an uncertain justificatory status, it does not follow that all do; and from the fact that some arguments for moral subscription are dubious, it does not follow that all are. Perhaps, somewhere in the melee of controversial moral standards and arguments, there are at least some standards on which all are agreed and to which subscription is demonstrably justified. This, I think, is just how things are. Within the reasonable plurality of moral standards there is an identifiable subset to which more or less everyone subscribes and for which the reasons to subscribe are compelling. There is a very broad consensus in society on some basic moral prohibitions (on stealing, cheating, causing harm, etc.) and prescriptions (to treat others fairly, help those in need, keep one’s promises, etc.). And there is a familiar rational justification for those basic moral standards whose cogency is hard to dispute. It is, briefly, that moral standards are justified when their currency in society serves to ameliorate the ever-present risk in human social groups of breakdowns in cooperation and outbreaks of conflict.

To my mind, there are several problems with the above passage. First of all, it seems that Hand is talking about the wrong kind of justification. In order to constitute knowledge – and thus in order to qualify as eligible input for educational transfer processes – moral beliefs need to enjoy a sufficient degree of epistemic justification. In contrast, Hand seems to talk about pragmatic justification: his idea is that we have pragmatic reasons to accept certain standards because they help us to sustain social cooperation – and not that we have epistemic reasons that speak for the truth of these standards. Footnote 9

But even putting this worry to the side, it still seems that Hand is also looking for the wrong kind of agreement: just as in other domains, educational knowledge transfer in the moral domain should be, given that it is feasible at all, informed by the relevant experts – and not by the general public. Given this, the kind of agreement that is necessary for educational knowledge transfer to be epistemically legitimate is agreement among the relevant experts – because as we have seen, it is exactly this kind of agreement whose absence potentially undermines the epistemic status of expert beliefs.

To be clear, this should obviously be a rather significant distinction. It is easily conceivable that there are moral questions which are almost completely uncontroversial among the general public, but highly controversial among moral experts – and vice versa. Furthermore, there might also be moral questions which are sufficiently uncontroversial among the relevant experts, but which haven ‘t even been considered by the general public. So at least against the background of the specific interpretation of the challenge of disagreement that has been developed in the last section, it seems that the question that needs to be answered in order to assess the efficacy of this challenge is not whether there are any moral principles that are sufficiently uncontroversial among the general public to be pragmatically justified, but whether there are any moral principles that are sufficiently uncontroversial among the relevant experts to be epistemically justified. In what follows, I would like to make some steps towards answering this question.

3.1 (Meta-)Ethical Agreement

One first obvious source of moral expert agreement are (i) first-order moral questions with regard to which the competing moral theories yield the same result and (ii) meta-ethical questions. With respect to these questions, the possibility of moral knowledge transmission seems to be untouched by the challenge of disagreement. And in fact, the 2020 PhilPapers Survey seems to support this assumption. For example, of the 227 meta-ethicists who participated in this study, 77.53% accept or lean toward cognitivism, and 65.35% accept or lean toward moral realism. With respect to the latter issue, the degree of controversy has indeed significantly decreased in comparison to 2009 (Bourget and Chalmers 2021 ). Given the prevalence of student statements like “When it comes to moral questions, there is no true or false” and “There are no moral facts”, it seems that these results will be of some didactical significance. Footnote 10 Furthermore, there also seems to be some striking agreement with respect to first-order moral questions. For example, 86.11% of professional ethicists Footnote 11 agree that abortion is generally permissible, 74.13% Footnote 12 agree that capital punishment is impermissible, and 74.26% agree that human genetic engineering is permissible. Footnote 13 And again, given how controversial these issues usually are among students, this result should be of some didactical significance. To be fair, the above results in no way suffice to establish any significant number of moral insights that could then be readily taken as the proper input of knowledge transfer processes. One first problem is that the available empirical evidence is still pretty meager: what we would need is a substantial body of empirical data that enables us to get a clearer picture of the scope and degree of moral agreement among the relevant experts. A second problem is rather philosophical in nature. That is, even if we knew exactly what moral philosophers agree on, there would still be the question of how much agreement is needed to allow for the possibility of knowledge transmission. Or, to put it differently: what degree of expert disagreement suffices to undermine the possibility of knowledge transmission? While any answer to this question depends on a variety of complicated issues, epistemologists do agree that numbers matter (Grundmann 2013 ). Footnote 14 In a situation where only a small group of experts deviate from the majority view, this level of disagreement won’t suffice to undermine the possibility of knowledge transmission. At the same time, it is not easy to determine any specific threshold above which disagreement starts to have sufficiently destructive epistemic implications. Solving this philosophical problem would also be of great help for estimating the exact scope of the challenge of disagreement for moral knowledge transfer. Nevertheless, the above considerations do show that it would be premature to simply dismiss any attempt to legitimize moral knowledge transfer in educational settings by vaguely pointing to the alleged pervasiveness of moral disagreement. While professional ethicists certainly disagree about many moral questions, there will also be a considerable amount of moral agreement.

3.2 Agreement on Second-Order Principles

What I would like to argue for in the remainder of this section is that even in cases where professional ethicists disagree, the transmission of moral knowledge is still possible. To see how, let’s start with a simple thought experiment developed by Matheson ( 2021 , p. 15):

Trina is travelling for work. When she travels for work, her work covers her travel costs upon receiving the receipts. On this trip, Trina has a particularly bad travel experience. Her travel experience is so bad that the airlines refunds the price of her return trip. Upon returning home, Trina is thinking about whether she should still submit the original receipt to her work since the refund was intended as compensation for a bad experience. Trina talks things over with her good friend Lesley. Trina and Lesley disagree about what is morally permissible here even though they agree about all the non-moral facts relevant to the issue.

What should Trina do in this scenario? Intuitively, it seems that under the described circumstances, Trina shouldn’t submit the receipt to her work. Furthermore, it seems that Trina is also in a position to know that she shouldn’t do this and that she would therefore be blameworthy if she decided to submit the receipt anyway. At the same time, Trina doesn’t know whether submitting the receipt would be morally permissible. To describe this peculiar case in a slightly improper way, we could say that although Trina doesn’t know what to do, she knows what to do given that she doesn’t know what to do . How can we put this more precisely? At this point, it is helpful to distinguish between different levels of decision-guiding norms. With respect to the relevant first-order norms, Trina is in a state of substantial uncertainty. Given her disagreement with her friend Lesley, she doesn’t know whether submitting the receipt would be a morally objectionable form of fraud, which would directly give her a first-order reason to not submit the receipt. However, it still seems that Trina is in a position to know perfectly well what she should do. In light of this, it looks like there is a different set of norms – second-order norms – that guide decisions under moral uncertainty. And in the above case, it is easily conceivable that Trina knows about the second-order norms guiding her decision while not knowing about the relevant first-order norms.

More specifically, the second-order moral norm that Matheson identifies on the basis of the above case is the following (see Matheson

MORAL CAUTION (MC): Having considered the moral status of doing action A in context C, if (i) subject S (epistemically) should believe or suspend judgment that doing A in C is a serious moral wrong, while (ii) S knows that refraining from doing A in C is not morally wrong, then S (morally) should not do A in C.

One immediate objection at this point is that this norm doesn ‘t tell us how to deal with , but only how to avoid states of substantive moral uncertainty. To counter this objection, it will help to look at cases of complete moral uncertainty , i.e. cases where the moral status of every available option is unclear. Consider, then, the following case from MacAskill et al. ( 2020 , p.16):

Susan is a doctor, who faces two sick individuals, Anne and Charlotte. Anne is a human patient, whereas Charlotte is a chimpanzee. They both suffer from the same condition and are about to die. Susan has a vial of a drug that can help. If she administers all of the drug to Anne, Anne will survive but with disability, at half the level of welfare she’d have if healthy.

Now consider the following: if Susan decides instead to give all of the drug to Charlotte, then Charlotte will survive with a slight disability at three quarters of the welfare that she’d have if she were healthy. Alternatively, if Susan splits the drug between the two, then they will both survive at a little less than 50% of the welfare that they’d have if they were healthy. Given this specification, we can now consider the rest of the case (MacAskill et al. 2020 , p. 17):

Susan is certain that the way to aggregate welfare is simply to sum it up, but is unsure about the value of the welfare of non-human animals. She thinks it is equally likely that chimpanzees’ welfare has no moral value and that chimpanzees’ welfare has the same moral value as human welfare. As she must act now, there is no way that she can improve her epistemic state with respect to the relative value of humans and chimpanzees. Her three options, then, are as follows: A: Give all of the drug to Anne. B: Split the drug. C: Give all of the drug to Charlotte.

Susan’s decision situation can be represented in the following table:

The crucial difference between this case and Trina’s is that in the above case, every option that is relevant to the decision situation is subject to substantive moral uncertainty. More specifically, given that Susan is unsure about the moral value of the welfare of non-human animals, she is not in a position to determine the relative choiceworthiness of any of the available options. To see this, suppose that chimpanzees’ welfare has no moral value at all. Against the background of this assumption, A is the best option and C is the worst option. However, if we suppose that chimpanzees’ welfare has the same moral value as human welfare, B will be the best option and A will be the worst option. So given that Susan is unsure about the moral value of chimpanzees’ welfare, she is in a state of substantive moral uncertainty with respect to each of the options available to her.

Let’s call cases like the above cases of complete moral uncertainty. The important point in our present context is that even in cases of complete moral uncertainty, there seem to be specific second-order norms that guide our decisions. For example, in the above case, it seems intuitive that it would be morally reckless for Susan not to choose option B. For given her uncertainty about the moral status of non-human animals, she would risk severe wrongdoing by choosing either option A or option C. However, Susan doesn’t know whether B really is the best option – if it turned out that chimpanzees’ welfare didn’t have any moral value, then A would be the best option. So if we suppose that Susan knows that she should choose option B, then her knowledge wouldn’t consist in first-order knowledge about what the morally best option is, but rather in second-order knowledge about what she should do given that she doesn’t know what the morally best option is – i.e. knowledge about second-order norms that guide our decisions under moral uncertainty.

While these first-order and second-order norms are epistemically independent in the way just described, they are still both moral norms. One just has to consider the kind of blame that the protagonists in our cases would deserve if they violated the second-order norms guiding their decisions: in such a case, we would say that they have made a moral mistake and that they accordingly deserve moral blame. Furthermore, while the specific hypothetical scenarios underlying the above cases are comparatively artificial, they also seem to have obvious implications for more realistic situations. For example, take Susan ‘s uncertainty with respect to chimpanzee welfare: just as Susan, many people are uncertain about the moral status that they should assign to non-human animals. And just as in Susan ‘s case, this uncertainty will have direct implications for their moral decisions. To see this, we can just apply the Moral Caution Principle to the situation that many people find themselves in with respect to the question of whether they should continue to consume animal products or adopt a vegan lifestyle. Given the increasing public awareness of the horrific conditions under which many animal products are produced, many of these people will be unsure whether continued consumption of these products would be morally permissible or not. At the same time, many people will plausibly assume that a vegan lifestyle is at least morally permissible. If we apply the Moral Caution Principle to this situation, it seems that it would directly require veganism. What these considerations show is that second-order moral norms, while usually being developed and discussed against the background of highly artificial and idealized counterfactual scenarios, are directly applicable to real-life contexts. In fact, Matheson himself has applied his principle to the question of whether eating meat is morally permissible and a number of further concrete moral problems like abortion and charitable giving (Matheson ).

So as far as the above considerations are convincing, there are substantive moral norms guiding our decisions that are epistemically accessible to us even in cases of moral uncertainty. This result should clearly have significant implications for the prospects of knowledge transmission accounts to adequately deal with the challenge of moral disagreement. The obvious idea at this point is that even in cases where the experts are uncertain about what is morally right, they can still tell us what we should do given that they are uncertain about what is morally right. Or to put it a little more formally: even in cases where the relevant first-order moral norms are subject to substantive expert disagreement, experts can still agree about the corresponding second-order norms that would therefore constitute the proper input of educational transfer processes. Given that these second-order norms, albeit their apparent abstractness, are directly applicable to many real-life situations, this result should be highly relevant to educational practice.

In light of this, there is a direct possibility of transmitting substantive moral insights even with respect to questions that are controversial among professional ethicists. This possibility consists in the transmission of knowledge about second-order moral norms that guide our decisions under moral uncertainty. One obvious objection at this point is that while the above strategy may indeed point to a specific theoretical possibility of transferring moral knowledge in the face of moral expert disagreement, it is still doomed to fail, because the second-order norms that it relies upon will again be subject to persistent expert disagreement. But to my mind, such skepticism is at least premature. First of all, it would have to be substantiated by concrete empirical evidence – and given how new the philosophical debate about moral uncertainty is, such evidence won’t be readily available. However, simply resorting to pessimistic platitudes about the inevitable controversiality of all philosophical questions won’t be enough, since as we have seen, there seems to be a surprising number of philosophical questions with respect to which the relevant experts agree. Given this, a more realistic prediction would be that at least some second-order moral norms will be controversial. If we assume that, then the proposed strategy will be inapplicable in some cases of first-order expert disagreement – namely in those cases in which no fitting second-order principle is available or in which the relevant second-order principles are subject to persistent expert disagreement. Nevertheless, it will still be applicable in some – and perhaps many – cases of first-order expert disagreement, and thereby effectively help to further mitigate the challenge of disagreement for moral knowledge transmission.

4 The Accuracy of the Challenge of Disagreement

In the last section, I have argued that the challenge of disagreement is not an effective challenge against knowledge transmission accounts of moral education: although it effectively undermines the possibility of knowledge transmission with respect to first-order moral propositions that are in fact controversial among moral experts, the transmission of knowledge about sufficiently uncontroversial first-order norms and about second-order norms that guide our decisions under moral uncertainty remains untouched. In this section, I would like to discuss the accuracy of the challenge of disagreement: are we really dealing with a specific challenge to knowledge transmission accounts of moral education, or does the underlying problem run deeper? In this context, I would like to focus on so-called skill- and virtue-based accounts, which have been particularly influential in the literature. One core idea behind these accounts is that if – given how controversial moral issues are within academic philosophy – students can’t just rely on moral experts in gaining moral insights, then they will have to develop these insights on their own. And to do this, they have to be provided with specific skills like critical reasoning skills (Musschenga ) and debating skills (Meyer 2011 ), but also emotional skills (Slote 2009 ) and general intellectual virtues like open-mindedness or tolerance (Haydon 2003 ). Michael Hand summarizes this idea as follows (Hand 2018 , p. 11):

A […] standard response to the problem of […] disagreement is the suggestion that we educate children about morality rather than in it. On this view we should make children aware of a broad range of moral codes and justificatory arguments, encourage them to subject those codes and arguments to critical scrutiny, and invite them to subscribe to whichever code they take to enjoy the strongest argumentative support. […] Our job as educators is to cultivate moral autonomy by enabling children to make their own independent judgements on the content and justification of morality.

In this passage, Hand rightly calls these competing accounts explicitly a ‚response’ to the challenge of disagreement. To appreciate the dialectical significance of this point, it is helpful to elaborate on it in a little more detail. If alternative accounts of moral education are to be read as a response to a specific objection against knowledge transmission accounts, this will already constitute a significant concession. More specifically, if proponents of skill- and virtue-based accounts have developed their theories as a reaction to specific problems of knowledge transmission accounts, this will indicate that they would in principle be willing to accept knowledge transmission accounts – given that those problems can be solved satisfactorily. And in fact, while many proponents of skill- and virtue-based accounts of moral education will plausibly also promote the development of intellectual skills and virtues as a value in itself, at least one important idea behind these accounts seems to be the following: just as educational measures in other domains, moral education would ideally – among other things – also aim at the transmission of substantive domain-specific knowledge. However, this is not how things are. In face of some regrettable epistemic peculiarities of the moral domain, we are in no position to simply pass moral knowledge on to future generations. Given this, we have no other choice than to enable students to make their own, independent moral judgements.

In what follows, I would like to argue that this line of thought is ultimately unconvincing, because skill- and virtue-based accounts of moral education are also heavily affected by the epistemically destructive implications of moral disagreement—and that the challenge of disagreement is therefore not a specific challenge for knowledge transmission accounts. Actually, on closer inspection, it is not at all clear how the acquisition of intellectual skills and virtues could serve as an adequate response to the challenge of disagreement. For instance, one just has to envision the situation that students will find themselves in after they have used all these skills and virtues to develop their own moral views. In fact, many of the beliefs that students will form will be controversial, both among professional philosophers and among their classmates. Whenever students take a stance on a controversial moral issue, they will inevitably find themselves disagreeing not only with their superiors, but also with their peers. And given that the epistemically destructive effects of these disagreements are equal to or greater than those of moral disagreements among professional philosophers, this will undermine the epistemic status of their beliefs. Footnote 15

At this point, it becomes clear why proponents of moral knowledge transmission and proponents of skill and virtue development are really in the same boat. One main motivation behind promoting the development of intellectual skills and virtues was that it allows students to arrive at well-formed moral beliefs that serve as a suitable basis for decisions and actions, even in cases where the relevant moral questions are controversial among experts. However, this is not the case. When it comes to moral questions that are controversial among experts, it is simply not possible for students to arrive at justified verdicts on their own, because the disagreeing experts undermine the justificatory status of any belief that the students could possibly form.

Given this, it seems that the challenge of disagreement is not a specific challenge to moral transmission accounts, but rather a general challenge to all accounts of moral education that aim at the development of moral insights. What’s more, it seems that knowledge transmission accounts are even less affected by the challenge of disagreement than their direct competitors. For instance, take cases where moral experts do in fact agree : in such cases, students who are encouraged to make up their own minds will likely still find themselves disagreeing with each other, which will again undermine their freshly formed beliefs’ justificatory status. In light of this, it looks like skill- or virtue-oriented accounts of moral education are actually more severely affected by the epistemically destructive implications of moral disagreement than knowledge transmission accounts.

That being said, it is important to stress that the above considerations are in no way meant as a general rejection of the idea that moral education should also aim at the development of various skills and virtues. Enabling students to make their own independent judgements is rightly widely regarded as a central educational goal, and should certainly be an integral part of their philosophical and moral education. However, this idea is in no way incompatible with knowledge transmission accounts of moral education. Passing moral insights on to future generations doesn’t mean to simply tell students what’s right and what’s wrong. Any pedagogically respectable realization of knowledge transfers will encourage and assist students to autonomously engage with the arguments and considerations that actually support the views that are presented to them. In fact, one might even argue that the transmission of moral knowledge already implies teaching the processes through which experts arrive at their conclusions. Understood in this way, enabling students to identify, evaluate and formulate ethical arguments and to critically assess the plausibility of different ethical theories is not just compatible with, but an integral part of moral knowledge transmission.

Throughout such a process, students will inevitably develop a variety of valuable skills and virtues. And this is a good thing: while there are plausibly some important moral questions with respect to which we can and should provide students with well-founded answers, simply informing students about these answers clearly won’t do. In order to have any impact on their practical decision-making, the moral principles that are taught in educational contexts need to be properly grasped by the students. Furthermore, students need to reliably identify the specific principles that are relevant to a given situation and then be able to adequately apply these principles in consideration of concrete situational circumstances. Lastly, students also need to critically reflect on the scope and the limitations of the principles that they have been taught in order to identify situations in which any definite moral judgement would be premature.

To be able to do all this, students obviously need to be provided with certain skills and virtues. So in a way, skill- and virtue-based accounts of moral education got it right by stressing the importance of the development of skills and virtues for successful moral education. However, they got it wrong by assuming that students can simply use these skills and virtues in order to arrive at well-founded judgements on moral questions that are even controversial among experts. In light of these considerations, it also gets clear that moral knowledge transmission – rightly understood – has nothing to do with wrongful manipulation or indoctrination. Indoctrination, as it is standardly defined, involves the attempt “to impart beliefs […] [to someone] in such a way that she comes to hold them non-rationally, on some other basis than the force of relevant evidence and argument” (Hand 2018 , 6). Purposefully providing students with those arguments and considerations that have been judged by experts to be most compelling seems like the direct opposite of indoctrination, since it helps students to arrive at the epistemically best supported moral views they can possibly have.

5 Conclusion

In this paper, I have discussed the so-called challenge of disagreement as a specific epistemic challenge to the idea that moral education should aim at the transmission of moral knowledge. Insofar as the above considerations are convincing, the observation that many if not most moral questions are controversial fails to pose a critical epistemic challenge to knowledge transmission accounts of moral education. First, the claim that many if not most moral questions are subject to persistent disagreement already requires some important relativization. While almost all moral questions may be controversial among laypeople, only disagreements among moral experts plausibly have the potential to undermine the educational transfer of moral knowledge. And although moral experts disagree about many moral questions, they apparently also agree on a surprising number of important moral issues. Second, there seems to be an attractive and hitherto neglected possibility of transferring moral knowledge even in cases where the relevant first-order moral questions are subject to persistent expert disagreement. This possibility consists in the transmission of knowledge about second-order moral norms that guide our decisions under moral uncertainty, and which are epistemically independent of the underlying first-order norms that are subject to disagreement. Given these considerations, the challenge of disagreement is not an effective challenge to the transmission of moral knowledge. Furthermore, it is important to notice that those controversies that actually persist among moral experts threaten to undermine not just the prospects of moral knowledge transmission, but all accounts of moral education that consider the attainment of moral insights to be an important goal of moral education. In this respect, the challenge of disagreement is also not a specific challenge for the transmission of moral knowledge.

In light of these results, it seems that knowledge transmission accounts of moral education are in a much better position than is usually expected to incorporate the fact that moral questions are notoriously controversial. As I stressed at the outset, this in no way means that knowledge transmission accounts are superior overall to alternative accounts of moral education. Indeed, there are a number of further important challenges that must be met in order to plausibilize the idea that moral knowledge can and should be transferred in educational settings. However, given the amount and severity of the moral problems that we currently face, we shouldn’t give up hope of also gaining and passing moral knowledge too quickly. Footnote 16

In this paper, I will use the terms ‚aim ‘ and ‚goal ‘ interchangeably.

This is one of the main motivations behind so-called constructivist educational environments, see e.g. O’Donnell 2012 .

In a way, the identified assumptions concerning the possibility of moral knowledge and moral expertise can also be seen as concessions to knowledge transmission accounts of moral education. However, I explicitly want to stay neutral with respect to the question of whether actual proponents of the challenge of disagreement accept these assumptions (i) because they believe them to be true or (ii) because they only want to make specific concessions to knowledge transmission accounts of moral education in order to argue that these accounts ultimately fail even against the background of these concessions.

In fact, it seems that when looking for moral expertise, one shouldn’t exclusively focus on professional philosophers. If we assume that moral expertise is ultimately grounded in specific argumentative skills and knowledge of ethical theories (see e.g. Singer 1982 ), being a professional philosopher – or even a professional ethicist – is neither necessary nor sufficient to count as a moral expert. Given this, my focus on professional philosophers in this paper is merely based on pragmatic considerations: First of all, if moral expertise is closely connected to specific argumentative skills and knowledge of ethical theories, being a professional philosopher will at least be a strong indication of moral expertise. Second, the distribution of moral views among professional philosophers has been subject to empirical research, which allows for a somewhat reliable estimation of the amount of moral disagreement among professional philosophers.

It is important to note that other authors have proposed alternative definitions of epistemic peerhood. For example, Thomas Kelly has suggested that two persons are epistemic peers when they are (i) equally familiar with the relevant evidence and (ii) equals with respect to general intellectual virtues (Kelly 2005 , 174). Alternatively, it has been suggested that two persons are epistemic peers when they are equally likely to be mistaken (Elga 2007 , 499; Wedgwood 2010 , 236). However, given that these definitions are more liberal than Christensen’s conception of epistemic peerhood, the following considerations are neutral with respect to this controversy.

While I will assume a conciliationist view on the significance of disagreement, I would explicitly like to stay neutral with respect to any deeper explanation of how exactly recognized disagreements undermine the epistemic status of our beliefs. One widespread view in this context is that disagreement situations provide defeaters for our beliefs – however, the exact nature of these defeaters is controversially discussed (see e.g. Constantin 2021 , ch. 6). In any case, it seems plausible that disagreement situations have epistemically destructive effects because they confront us with our epistemic limitations – or as David Christensen puts it (Christensen 2007 , 187 f.): ‚We all live out our lives in states of epistemic imperfection. […] One fairly common situation that may present opportunities for improvement is that of discovering that another person's belief on a given topic differs markedly from one’s own.‘ In this respect, conciliationism might be seen as a non-ideal epistemological theory: It tells us how to adequately deal with our epistemic limitations.

For a detailed discussion of the epistemic implications of disagreements with epistemic inferiors , see Priest 2016 .

While the conditions for epistemic peerhood are sometimes criticized as being unrealistically strict, it seems that these conditions are plausibly often met in academic contexts. Just consider the striking degree of epistemic homogeneity between professional philosophers – they usually have equal academic credentials and a comparable level of competence. Furthermore, they are equally familiar with the relevant literature and acquainted with the same set of arguments. Given this, the kind of disagreement situations that professonal ethicists find themselves in seem sufficiently similar to artificial situations like the Restaurant Case.

One objection that immediately suggests itself at this point is that the above considerations fail to appreciate the uniqueness of moral disagreements. To my mind, this objection seems ad hoc – why should moral disagreements behave epistemically different than other kinds of disagreement? To establish such a fundamental difference, one would first need to identify some special feature of moral disagreements that could properly explain their alleged epistemic innocence. For example, it has been argued that some of our beliefs – including our political, moral and religious beliefs – are at least partially based on private evidence (see e.g. Feldman 2007 ; Rosen 2001 ; van Inwagen 1996 ). However, even if that were the case, conflicting beliefs of other people that are based on private evidence would still have epistemically destructive effects, because the mere fact that there is evidence that supports a conflicting belief already speaks against the epistemic quality of one’s own belief, even if that evidence is inaccessible (Feldman 2007 ). According to another suggestion, the epistemic peculiarity of moral disagreements lies in the fact that these disagreements are grounded in differing, but equally reasonable evaluations of the available evidence (for a critical discussion of this claim, see e.g. Ballantyne and Coffman 2011 ; Brueckner and Bundy 2012 ; Schoenfield 2014 ). However, even if we accepted this suggestion, it would at best show that conflicting moral beliefs of other people don’t speak against the reasonableness of our own beliefs. But as long as we assume that only one side of a moral disagreement can be correct, they would still speak against the truth of our own beliefs and are thus epistemically destructive (Balg 2021a , pp. 73 ff.). According to the last suggestion that I would like to discuss here, the epistemic peculiarity of moral disagreements lies in the fact that the truth values of moral beliefs are relative to personal standards, so that conflicting moral beliefs of different persons can be true at the same time (see e.g. Kölbel 2004 ). While such a relativistic view would indeed speak against the epistemic toxicity of diverging moral beliefs, it is also highly controversial and likely to be rejected by the majority of professional philosophers. One reason for this reluctance is the worry that moral relativism doesn’t even allow for the bare existence of moral disagreement (see e.g. Lasersohn 2005 ; Wright 2001 ). So it seems that establishing a fundamental epistemic difference between moral and non-moral disagreements is no easy task. Although there are some features that have been suggested as possible epistemic peculiarities of moral disagreements in the literature, these features would in no way suffice to show that there are genuine moral disagreements with epistemic peers that are still epistemically innocuous.

In fact, in some of his other work, Hand seems to explicitly endorse a radical pluralism with respect to the kind of justification that moral standards can enjoy in order to qualify as eligible input for educational transfer processes. For example, in his book “A Theory of Moral Education”, Hand writes (Hand 2018 , p. 69):

[Recognising] that the problem-of-sociality justification is sound is quite compatible with believing that some other putative justification for subscribing to moral standards is also sound. It is no part of the foregoing argument that this is the only kind of good reason we could have for […] subscription to standards. It may turn out to be the case that basic moral standards are justified both by their capacity to avert conflict and sustain cooperation in human social groups and, say, by their divine authorization, or by an imperative of pure practical reason […]. Different justifications for the same standards can sit quite happily alongside each other; acceptance of one does not necessitate rejection of all others.

Non-cognitivist and anti-realist statements like the above can be seen as typical expressions of a well-known phenomenon that is discussed in the didactical literature under the label “student relativism” (for an overview, see Pfister 2019 ).

N  = 136. All these numbers are based on the answers of all respondents who named “applied ethics” as their area of specialization.

One reason why this question can’t be answered on a general level is that the epistemic significance of expert agreement depends (i) on the exact number of the agreeing experts and (ii) on the degree to which these experts came to their respective verdicts independently: according to Condorcet’s jury theorem, an increasing group of people who (i) have a individual reliability that is higher than 50% and (ii) independently came to the same conclusion approach a cumulative reliability of 100%. In light of this, it gets clear why identifying the point at which disagreement becomes epistemically irrelevant is not only complicated, but needs to be done on a case-by-case basis.

Furthermore, it is important at this point to carefully distinguish between different epistemic contexts. While it seems epistemically legitimate to ignore sufficiently small groups of disagreeing experts in educational contexts , it would clearly be illegitimate to do so in academic contexts – after all, a small chance will always remain for the majority view to turn out false (for a detailed discussion of such a distinction, see e.g. Balg 2021b , 64 ff.). For example, it seems completely unproblematic to educate children about the risks and dangers of global warming while at the same time ignoring critical views that contradict the scientific consensus of climate change. However, it would also be misguided to prematurely dismiss such critical voices within academic research – after all, they could surprisingly turn out to be true. One important implication of this view is that educational programs that are explicitly directed at the transmission of knowledge will sometimes end up transferring false beliefs. At the same time, this needn’t be a problematic result – for example, it is not surprising at all that students learn different things in science classes today than they did 200 years ago.

For a discussion of the epistemically destructive effects of disagreements with one’s epistemic superiors, see e.g. Constantin and Grundmann 2018 .

In fact, it seems that besides academic contexts, the educational system is one of the few real-life contexts where the highly artificial conditions for epistemic peerhood are plausibly often met. At least until they enter the university level, students are usually the same age. Furthermore, they have been provided with the same body of arguments as a basis for classroom discussion and have had the same amount of time to evaluate these arguments. Lastly, at least in some countries, students are grouped together on the basis of their grades, which further increases their epistemic homogeneity. Given all these peculiarities of the educational system, disagreements between students often have a remarking similarity with highly idealized scenarios like the Restaurant case.

I would like to thank four anonymous reviewers for a number of very helpful comments on earlier versions of this paper.

Balg D (2021a) Live and let live. A critique of intellectual tolerance. Springer, Berlin

Google Scholar  

Balg D (2021b) Toleranz. Was müssen wir aushalten? Metzler, Heidelberg

Book   Google Scholar  

Ballantyne N, Coffman E (2011) Uniqueness, evidence, and rationality. Philosophers’ Imprint 11:1–13

Bourget D, Chalmers DJ (2021) Philosophers on philosophy: The PhilPapers 2020 Survey. https://survey2020.philpeople.org . Accessed 24 Mar 2022

Bourget D, Chalmers DJ (2014) What do philosophers believe? Philos Stud 170:465–500. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-013-0259-7

Article   Google Scholar  

Brueckner A, Bundy A (2012) On “Epistemic Permissiveness.” Synthese 188:165–177. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-011-9921-9

Article   MathSciNet   Google Scholar  

Christensen D (2007) Epistemology of disagreement: the good news. Philos Rev 116:187–217. https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-2006-035

Christensen D (2009) Disagreement as evidence. The epistemology of controversy. Philosophy Compass 4:756–767. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1747-9991.2009.00237.x

Constantin J (2021) Epistemic defeat. De Gruyter, Berlin

Constantin J, Grundmann T (2018) Epistemic authority. Preemption through source sensitive defeat. Synthese 197:4109–4130. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-01923-x

Driver J (2006) Autonomy and the asymmetry problem for moral expertise. Philos Stud 128:619–644. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-004-7825-y

Elga A (2007) Reflection and disagreement. Noûs 41:478–502. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-0068.2007.00656.x

Feldman R (2007) Reasonable religious disagreements. In: Antony LM (ed) Philosophers without Gods. Meditations on atheism and the secular life. OUP, Oxford, pp 194–214

Chapter   Google Scholar  

Giesinger J (2021) Vermitteln und Mitteilen – Die Meinung der Lehrperson in der Diskussion kontroverser Themen. In: Drerup J, Zulaica y Mugica M, Yacek D (eds) Dürfen Lehrer ihre Meinung sagen? Demokratische Bildung und die Kontroverse über Kontroversitätsgebote. Kohlhammer, Stuttgart, pp 19–30

Goldberg S (2010) Relying on others. OUP, Oxford

Goldman AI (2006) Social epistemology, theory of evidence, and intelligent design. Deciding what to teach. South J Philos 44:1–22. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.2041-6962.2006.tb00026.x

Grundmann T (2013) Doubts about philosophy? The alleged challenge from disagreement. In: Henning T, Schweikard D (eds) Knowledge, virtue, and action. Putting epistemic virtues to work. Routledge, London, pp 72–98

Grundmann T (2019) How to respond rationally to peer disagreement. The preemption view. Philos Issues 29:129–142. https://doi.org/10.1111/phis.12144

Hand M (2014) Towards a theory of moral education. J Philos Educ 48:519–532. https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-9752.12116

Hand M (2018) A theory of moral education. Routledge, London

Haydon G (2003) Moral education. In: Curren R (ed) A companion to the philosophy of education. Blackwell, Malden, pp 320–331

Kelly T (2005) The epistemic significance of disagreement. In: Hawthorne J, Gendler T (eds) Oxford studies in epistemology, vol 1. OUP, Oxford, pp 167–196

Kelly T (2011) Peer disagreement and higher-order evidence. In: Goldman AI, Whitcomb D (eds) Social epistemology. Essential readings. OUP, Oxford, pp 183–221

Kölbel M (2004) Indexical relativism versus genuine relativism. Int J Philos Stud 12:297–313. https://doi.org/10.1080/0967255042000243966

Lasersohn P (2005) Context dependence, disagreement, and predicates of personal taste. Linguist Philos 28:643–686. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-005-0596-x

MacAskill W, Bykvist K, Ord T (2020) Moral Uncertainty. OUP, Oxford

Matheson J (2021) Applying Moral caution in the face of disagreement. Ethical Theory Moral Pract. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-021-10155-x

Meyer K (2011) Moralische Bildung im Philosophie- und Ethikunterricht. In: Limbourg M, Steins G (eds) Sozialerziehung in der Schule. VS Verlag für Sozialwissenschaften, Wiesbaden, pp 223–237

Musschenga AW (2009) Moral intuitions, moral expertise and moral reasoning. J Philos Educ 43:597–613. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9752.2009.00707.x

O’Donnell AM (2012) Constructivism. In: Harris KR, Graham S, Urdan T, McCormick CB, Sinatra GM, Sweller J (eds) APA educational psychology handbook, Vol. 1. Theories, constructs, and critical issues. American Psychological Association, Washington D.C., pp 61–84

Pfister J (2019) Classification of strategies for dealing with student relativism and the epistemic conceptual change strategy. Teach Philos 42:221–246. https://doi.org/10.5840/teachphil2019730107

Priest M (2016) Inferior disagreement. Acta Analytica 31:263–283. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-015-0277-5

Rosen G (2001) Nominalism, naturalism, philosophical relativism. Noûs 35:69–91. https://doi.org/10.1111/0029-4624.35.s15.4

Schoenfield M (2014) Permission to believe. Noûs 48:193–218. https://doi.org/10.1111/nous.12006

Singer P (1982) How do we decide? Hastings Cent Rep 12:9–11. https://doi.org/10.2307/3561822

Article   CAS   PubMed   Google Scholar  

Slote M (2009) Caring, empathy and moral education. In: Siegel H (ed) The Oxford handbook of philosophy of education. OUP, Oxford, pp 211–226

van Inwagen P (1996) It is wrong, everywhere, always, for anyone, to believe anything upon insufficient evidence. In: Jordan J (ed) Faith, freedom, and rationality. Philosophy of religion today. Rowman & Littlefield, Lanham, pp 137–154

Wedgwood R (2010) The moral evil demons. In: Feldman R, Warfield TA (eds) disagreement. OUP, Oxford, pp 216–246

Wright C (2001) On being in a quandary. Relativism vagueness logical revisionism. Mind 110:45–98. https://doi.org/10.1093/mind/110.437.45

Download references

Open Access funding enabled and organized by Projekt DEAL.

Author information

Authors and affiliations.

Philosophy Department, University of Mainz, 55099, Mainz, Germany

Dominik Balg

You can also search for this author in PubMed   Google Scholar

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Dominik Balg .

Ethics declarations

Declarations.

• The author did not receive support from any organization for the submitted work.

• No funding was received to assist with the preparation of this manuscript.

• No funding was received for writing this article.

• No funds, grants, or other support was received.

• The author has no relevant financial or non-financial interests to disclose.

• The author has no competing interests to declare that are relevant to the content of this article.

• The author certifies that he has no affiliations with or involvement in any organization or entity with any financial interest or non-financial interest in the subject matter or materials discussed in this manuscript.

• The author has no financial or proprietary interests in any material discussed in this article.

Additional information

Publisher's note.

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Open Access This article is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License, which permits use, sharing, adaptation, distribution and reproduction in any medium or format, as long as you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons licence, and indicate if changes were made. The images or other third party material in this article are included in the article's Creative Commons licence, unless indicated otherwise in a credit line to the material. If material is not included in the article's Creative Commons licence and your intended use is not permitted by statutory regulation or exceeds the permitted use, you will need to obtain permission directly from the copyright holder. To view a copy of this licence, visit http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/ .

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Balg, D. Moral Disagreement and Moral Education: What’s the Problem?. Ethic Theory Moral Prac 27 , 5–24 (2024). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-023-10399-9

Download citation

Accepted : 24 May 2023

Published : 05 June 2023

Issue Date : March 2024

DOI : https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-023-10399-9

Share this article

Anyone you share the following link with will be able to read this content:

Sorry, a shareable link is not currently available for this article.

Provided by the Springer Nature SharedIt content-sharing initiative

  • Moral education
  • Moral disagreement
  • Moral knowledge
  • Moral uncertainty
  • Find a journal
  • Publish with us
  • Track your research

180 Ethics Topics & Ethical Questions to Debate

Our code of ethics is derived from what we think is right or wrong. On top of that, we have to agree to the moral standards established by the society we live in. Conventional norms generally label theft, murder, or harassment as bad. However, there are many influences that impact our considerations and understanding of ethics.

Our specialists will write a custom essay specially for you!

Ethics is a branch of philosophy that studies moral issues. This article outlines the three different types of ethics and presents a list of compelling ethics topics for essays and research papers, as well as ethical questions to debate.

You don’t know how to write about ethics or which ethical argument topic to choose for your paper? Maybe your assignment deadline is dreadfully looming over you? Our custom writing service is happy to help you craft a fantastic essay on ethics whenever the need arises.

🔝 Top 10 Ethical Topics

  • 🧑🤝🧑Types of Ethics
  • 🤔 Ethical Issues
  • 🖥️ Computer Ethics
  • 🧬 Bioethics
  • 🚓👮 Criminal Justice
  • ⚖️ Ethical Dilemmas

⭐ Top 10 Ethics Topics to Debate

😈 ethical questions to debate, 🔍 references.

  • Religious beliefs vs. medical care
  • Issues behind unpaid internships
  • Toxic environment at the workplace
  • The dilemma of reporting an accident
  • Should one’s political leanings be private?
  • The limits of doctor-patient confidentiality
  • Is it ethical to pay children for good grades?
  • Ethics at the workplace and discrimination
  • Should social media be allowed at the workplace?
  • Promotion of environmental responsibility in business

🧑🤝🧑 Types of Ethics

Modern philosophy splits ethics into three groups: metaethics, normative ethics, and applied ethics.

  • The core question of metaethics is: “What is morality, and where does it come from?” It is also concerned with the emergence of human values, motivation, and reasoning.
  • Normative ethics seeks to answer the question, “How should I act?” An example of a normative moral theory is Kant’s Categorical Imperative: Act only according to that maxim whereby you can, at the same time, will that it should become a universal law . In other words: be kind.
  • Applied ethics seeks to apply moral considerations into real-life controversial subjects. Its contents can vary greatly and touch bioethics as well as criminal justice. It studies specific actions and practices from the point of moral acceptance.

Virtues are necessary.

However, ethics does not end with these three types. Over the centuries, philosophers have proposed various ethical theories. Their four general categories are deontological, utilitarian, right, and virtue ethics.

  • A deontologist is a person with a set of moral duties from which they will not adhere. When faced with an ethical conflict, they will always act according to their self-proclaimed obligations.
  • For a utilitarian , a decision needs to yield the greatest benefit for the majority.
  • If rights are the root of an ethical theory, these are the highest priority. A person’s rights can either be established in a society by law or bestowed from one individual upon another.
  • Judging someone by virtue means considering a person’s character rather than their actions. Here, an individual’s reputation, motivation, and ethics play a crucial role.

Now that you know the basics, you have the perfect ground to start your ethics essay.

Just in 1 hour! We will write you a plagiarism-free paper in hardly more than 1 hour

🤔 Ethical Topics for an Essay

Ethical issues are situations in which an individual needs to evaluate which course of action is morally right. Essays on this topic shine a light on difficult questions. Therefore, students need to defend their position convincingly.

  • Discuss what we should do about climate change . 
  • What are the moral problems surrounding abortion ? 
  • Can we still justify eating meat? 
  • Investigate the use of plastic in the beauty industry. 
  • Is it unethical to be extremely rich? 
  • Should you buy Nestlé products despite the fact that the company privatizes water? 
  • Is the unequal distribution of wealth unethical? 
  • Discuss how workplace ethics should take sexism into account. 
  • What can we do to combat racism ? 
  • Why are LGBT + people discriminated against? 
  • Should euthanasia be legal? 
  • Can war be ethical? 
  • Should schools punish students for attending the Fridays for Future protests? 
  • Would drug use be unethical if it were legal? 
  • Explain the moral problems that come with automating jobs . 

The Ten Commandments.

  • Is it ethical to hire someone to do assignments for you? 
  • How far should everyone’s right to privacy go? 
  • Is using animals for scientific testing unethical? 
  • How should governments deal with refugees ? 
  • Discuss the carbon impact of having children. 
  • Can modern societies still be held accountable for what their nation did in the past? 
  • Analyze the benefits and disadvantages of universal income . 
  • How much control should the state have on the press? 
  • Should schools teach religion ? 
  • What are ethical concerns regarding downloading media from the internet? 

🖥️ Computer Ethics Essay Topics

The advent of information technology has altered every aspect of our lives. Computer ethics applies traditional moral theories to everything surrounding computers and cyber security. The list below contains enthralling ethical topics concerned with the realm of computing.

  • How much work should we leave entirely to computers? 
  • Discuss the dangers of storing vulnerable data online. 
  • Are computers secure enough to contain so much information about our lives? 
  • Discuss if hacking can be morally justified. 
  • Examine privacy-related concerns regarding computers . 
  • Should all software be free? 
  • How can you legitimize the possession of a computer algorithm patent? 
  • What can be done to prevent cyberbullying ? 
  • Investigate the moral effects anonymity has on internet users. 
  • Whose laws apply if you wish to protect your rights online? 
  • Discuss how the necessity to own a computer impacts poorer nations and people. 
  • Which ethical problems can people face due to the internet’s possibilities? 
  • When is sabotaging another person’s computer justified? 
  • Analyze the social responsibility that comes with developing new software. 
  • Are computer crimes less harmful than crimes against humans? 
  • Who owns information that is distributed online? 
  • What is more important: easy accessibility or privacy? 
  • Investigate the moral problems associated with AI . 
  • If a computer makes a critical mistake, whose fault is it? 
  • Discuss the importance of netiquette. 
  • How should tech companies deal with ethical problems? 
  • Can AI algorithms ensure ethical behavior? 
  • Why do tech companies need ethics boards? 
  • Which ethical conflicts appear when using drones ? 
  • Investigate racial bias in facial recognition systems. 

🏅 Sports Ethics Topics for a Paper

Morality in sports is based on integrity, respect, responsibility, and fairness. Often, this puts athletes into a dilemma: do I want to be ethical, or do I want to win? Answering these questions is not always easy. The following list compiles sports topics for a research paper on ethics.

  • What are moral complications when using enhancement drugs? 
  • Is gamesmanship unethical? 
  • How important is ethics in sports? 
  • Discuss the moral responsibilities of athletes . 
  • What are ethical reasons to pay college athletes ? 
  • Investigate the ethical implications of kneeling for the national anthem . 
  • Can college sports and the principles of higher education go hand in hand? 
  • Investigate the sexist bias in sports. 
  • Was it selfish when the American female soccer team went to court to demand equal pay? 

Thomas A. Edison quote.

  • What moral obligations do universities have towards their athletes? 
  • When can you justify cheating ? 
  • Concerning the environment, how can professional sports events be ethical? 
  • Which ethical issues do healthcare workers have concerning sportspeople? 
  • Which moral duties do teams’ coaches have? 
  • Are the extremely high salaries of sports professionals justified? 
  • In 2003, the Olympics abolished the wild card system. Was that fair? 
  • Because of the Paralympics, disabled athletes cannot take part in the real Olympics. Is that discriminatory? 
  • Discuss how money influences the fairness of a sport. 
  • Debate if and how children are exploited to become elite athletes. 
  • Which moral duties should a good sport follow? 
  • How much should parents get involved in their child’s physical education ? 
  • Investigate if everyday codes of ethics should apply to sports. 
  • Discuss the ethical implications of motorsports. 
  • Who is responsible if a player gets injured? 
  • Are referees always fair? 

🧬 Bioethics Topics for an Essay

Bioethics comes into play when we talk about life and health. It expands from genetics to neurology and even plastic surgery. In the name of the common good, researchers often find themselves in conflicting positions. This makes bioethics an especially exciting topic to write about.

  • Discuss the moral conflicts of genetic engineering . 
  • What are the ethical responsibilities associated with using CRISPR ? 
  • Investigate the problems of stem cell research . 
  • When can humans be used for drug testing ? 
  • Should vaccinations be mandatory for everyone? 
  • Investigate the ethics that apply to a medical worker. 
  • Discuss the harmful effects of plastic surgery . 
  • Should a person who is brain dead be kept alive? 
  • Is it just that medical care is linked to an individual’s ability to pay? 
  • Should everyone be an organ donor by default? 
  • What is more important: a person’s right to privacy or the information of at-risk relatives? 
  • Is prenatal invasive testing ethical? 
  • Should neuroenhancement drugs be legal? 
  • Discuss ethical conflicts concerning Disclosure and Barring Service. 
  • Is it ethical to improve memory functions with brain stimulation ? 
  • Analyze the ethical issues concerning precision medicine. 
  • What are the problems of surrogacy ? 
  • Should medical personnel collect healthy tissues of a deceased person without their consent? 

Bioethics is closely connected with the fields of technology, medicine, politics, philosophy, and law,

  • What should be done with the child of a brain-dead pregnant woman? 
  • How important is a subject’s anonymity during research? 
  • Discuss the ethics of shared decision-making . 
  • How much responsibility do mentally challenged people carry for their actions? 
  • Was Sweden right not to impose strict lockdown rules during the COVID-19 pandemic? 
  • To what extent are businesses responsible for their employees’ health? 
  • Should universal healthcare be free? 

🚓👮 Criminal Justice Ethics Topics to Write About

Law enforcers should always act ethically. Unfortunately, it is not always the case. Police officers and attorneys often end up in morally ambiguous situations. In many cases, they don’t do what the public deems the right thing. Below are the examples of criminal justice ethics topics.

Receive a plagiarism-free paper tailored to your instructions. Cut 20% off your first order!

  • When is it legitimate for a police officer to use violence? 
  • How can an officer remain impartial? 
  • Should law enforcement visibly wear guns in public? 
  • How much force is too much? 
  • Investigate possible ethical implications associated with true crime podcasts. 
  • Should prostitution be legal in the US? 
  • How ethical is interrogation ? 
  • Can torture be justified? 
  • Discuss the ethical consequences of lying when working in criminal justice . 
  • Is working undercover deception? 
  • Debate whether it is an American citizen’s moral duty to participate in jury duty. 
  • Should the police be allowed to access everyone’s data? 
  • Discuss the moral complications of “innocent until proven guilty.” 
  • Should convicted pedophiles be allowed to see their children? 
  • Can teaching ethics at schools prevent crime? 
  • Analyze ethical problems of the Stanford Prison Experiment . 
  • Should NATO have become involved in America’s Afghan war ? 
  • What are the ethical implications of shooter drills at school? 
  • Was Edward Snowden morally in the wrong? 
  • How should we deal with child soldiers ? 
  • Discuss if the prosecution of Julian Assange is justified. 
  • Examine the ethical problems of private prisons . 
  • What moral obligations should someone consider when granting prisoners the right to work? 
  • When is capital punishment justified? 
  • Is it ethical to incarcerate juvenile offenders ? 

⚖️ Ethical Dilemma Topics to Write About

An ethical issue becomes a dilemma when different moral standards clash with each other. In this situation, it is impossible to find a path to an ethically permissible solution that is unambiguous. The following sample topics are a solid base to start a discussion on morals.

  • Should parents watch over what their children do on the internet? 
  • Would you report an accident you caused if there are no witnesses? 
  • What should a doctor do if a patient refuses life-saving treatment for religious reasons? 
  • Should you turn down a client if their political views do not match yours? 
  • Would you promote something you are not convinced of to get money? 
  • Should you lie to land a job that gets you out of poverty? 

Ethical dilemmas.

  • Your partner cheated on you. Now, you get the chance to take your revenge with someone you really like. Would you do it? 
  • Should students use automated writing tools like free thesis generators , summarizers, and paraphrasers? 
  • Your teacher is continuously mocking your classmate. You are a teacher’s pet. Would you speak up? 
  • Your son likes to wear dresses. One day, he asks if he can wear one to school. Will you let him? 
  • You are very religious. Your daughter wants to get married to another woman and invites you to her wedding. What will you do? 
  • Prenatal testing showed that your unborn child has a disability. Would you terminate pregnancy? 
  • You are in a long-term relationship. Suddenly, your partner gets a job offer in another part of the world. What would you do? 
  • You have a terminal illness . This makes you a financial burden to your relatives. Are you obliged towards them to quit your treatment? 
  • You have a red and a blue candy bar. Blue is your favorite, but you also know that it’s your friend’s favorite. Will you give it to them? 
  • A friend asked you for a loan. Since then, they have not given you anything back. They are still not wholly stable financially. Will you ask them to return the money? 
  • Your grandma passed away and bequeathed her favorite mink coat to you. You are a vegan. What do you do? 
  • A few years ago, you borrowed a gun from a friend. Now, they ask for it back, but their mental state seems to be rapidly deteriorating. This makes you scared they are going to shoot someone, or themselves. What do you do? 
  • You find out that your friend cheats on their spouse. You are close friends with their family. Will you tell on them? 
  • For your birthday, your friend gave you a sweater they’ve made themselves. You think it’s ugly. Do you tell them? 
  • You are a vegan . Should you buy vegan products which are highly problematic to produce? 
  • You are in a restaurant. Your order arrives too late. The waitress looks stressed. Will you make her take it back? 
  • You went to the store and bought a new, expensive item. The clerk gives you too much change. Do you give it back? 
  • You are walking with a friend and find $50 on the floor. Would you share it with them? 
  • Your child firmly believes in Santa Claus. One Christmas , they start suspecting that he is not real. What do you do? 
  • Is having pets ethical?
  • Can eating meat be justified?
  • Should we defund the police?
  • Should atomic bombs be banned?
  • Can discrimination be justified?
  • Is it ethical to ask someone’s age?
  • Should children get paid for chores?
  • Is it unprofessional to send voice messages?
  • Should children be allowed to vote?
  • Should influencers promote products they don’t use?
  • Should there be any limitations to doctor and patient confidentiality?
  • Should physician-assisted suicide be allowed?
  • Can teenagers get plastic surgery?
  • What to do when you find out that your relative has committed an offense?
  • What to do when you see your friend cheating on the exam?
  • Should sportsmen be paid more than teachers?
  • Should gender quotas be used during parliamentary elections?
  • Do companies have the right to collect information about their customers?
  • Can politicians appeal to religious issues during electoral campaigns?
  • Should fake news be censored in a democratic society?

We hope that in this list you’ve found the ethics topic that fits you the best. Good luck with your assignment!

Further reading:

  • 430 Philosophy Topics & Questions for Your Essay
  • 226 Research Topics on Criminal Justice & Criminology
  • 512 Research Topics on HumSS (Humanities & Social Sciences)
  • 204 Research Topics on Technology & Computer Science
  • What’s the Difference Between Morality and Ethics?: Britannica
  • What is Ethics?: Santa Clara University
  • Ethics: Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
  • Metaethics: Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
  • Ethical Issues: Idaho State University
  • The Problem with AI Ethics: The Verge
  • Sports Ethics: Santa Clara University
  • What Is Bioethics?: Michigan State University
  • Ethics in Criminal Justice: Campbellsville University
  • Kant’s Formula of Universal Law: Harvard University
  • Share to Facebook
  • Share to Twitter
  • Share to LinkedIn
  • Share to email

457 Definition Essay Topics and Writing Tips

A definition explains the meaning of a term or a concept. In a dictionary, you’ll find a definition in a single sentence. A definition paper, however, encompasses several paragraphs. Such an essay, amongst other things, can include personal experience and examples. To write a successful definition paper, you need to...

270 Good Descriptive Essay Topics and Writing Tips

As simple as it is, the purpose of the descriptive essay is to explain or portray its subject. It can focus on any topic or issue you want to write about. Be sure that any middle school, high school, or college student can manage this type of creative writing assignment!...

160+ Best Rhetorical Analysis Topics

Rhetorical analysis essay focuses on assessing the method used for delivering a message. This assignment isn’t about giving an opinion on the topic. The purpose is to analyze how the author presents the argument and whether or not they succeeded. Keep reading to find out more strategies and prompts for...

164 Narrative Essay Topics for School & College Students

A narrative essay tells a story about a series of events. At the core of this kind of essay can be a personal experience or a fictional plot. Any story can be a basis for a narrative essay! Narratives can look similar to descriptions. Still, they are different. A descriptive...

200 Process Essay Topics

Similar to the instructions in a recipe book, process essays convey information in a step-by-step format. In this type of paper, you follow a structured chronological process. You can also call it a how-to essay. A closely related type is a process analysis essay. Here you have to carefully consider...

150 Classification Essay Topics and Ideas

In a classification essay, you divide the subject into categories. To create these categories, you single out certain attributes of things. You can classify them according to their characteristics, themes, or traits. Sounds complicated? Be sure that any high school or college student can manage this type of essay!

200 Excellent Evaluation Essay Topics

Throughout your high school years, you are likely to write many evaluative papers. In an evaluation essay you aim is to justify your point of view through evidence.

240 Immigration Essay Topics

Immigration is a permanent move to a foreign country. It takes place all over the globe, including the United States. It played an important role in history, and it continues to influence society today. This article offers a variety of immigration essay topics. They are suitable for college-level works, as...

440 Good Compare and Contrast Essay Topics

Should you buy a green or a red apple? Before making a decision, people often compare their options. In a compare and contrast essay, you analyze the similarities and differences between certain things. In this article, you’ll find interesting and easy compare and contrast essay topics for college, high school...

210 Good Opinion Topics for Essays

An opinion essay requires a student to present a point of view on a chosen subject and back it up with substantial evidence. Like in a debate, the writer has to give their opinion and defend it while using scholarly resources. This article will help you find a good opinion...

120+ Micro- & Macroeconomics Research Topics

It would be great if economics in college would just teach you how to save and make money. In reality, however, students usually write research papers on micro- and macroeconomics topics to learn about the production and consumption of goods on an international level.

417 Business Topics & Research Titles about Business

The corporate world is the world of the future – there’s no doubt about that. And education in ABM will help you conquer it! What is ABM strand, exactly? ABM stands for Accountancy, Business, and Management. Future leaders and entrepreneurs pursue education in this field to learn the skills essential...

Study Paragraphs

Essay on Importance of Moral Education For Students

In today’s society, morality and etiquette are both subjective and often defined by the individual. In this article, we will discuss some of the major perspectives on moral education for students.

Table of Contents

The Importance of Moral Education Essay for Students

Moral education is essential for students to have in order to create good, ethical citizens. It teaches students about right and wrong, values, and the responsibilities that come with having those values. It also helps students make informed decisions and handle difficult situations.

Moral education should start early in a student’s life. Many people believe that moral education starts with kindergarten or preschool, when children are still developing their sense of right and wrong. However, moral education can also be taught in high school or college.

There are many benefits to teaching moral education in schools. For one, it helps students develop a strong character. Character is critical in life, and it’s important for students to learn how to build healthy relationships, cope with stress, and handle adversity. Moral education also teaches students how to think critically and solve problems. This skill set is valuable in any field, but is especially important in fields such as law, business, journalism, engineering, and medicine.

Unfortunately, not all schools provide adequate moral education. In fact, according to the National Association of School Psychologists (NASP), only about one-third of U.S. schools offer any type of moral education at all (NASP 2013

How to Increase Moral Education for Students

Moral education is an important part of a child’s development. It teaches them how to make good decisions and behave ethically. It also helps them understand the consequences of their actions.

There are many benefits to moral education for students. They learn to think critically and to be self-aware. They also learn how to cooperate and work together. In addition, they learn how to treat others ethically, which can help them become responsible citizens in the future.

Moral education is important for all students, but it is particularly important for students who are growing up in a time when there are more choices than ever before. Today’s children face difficult decisions every day, and they need guidance in making the right ones. Moral education gives them the skills they need to make well-informed choices, and it helps them develop a sense of responsibility and compassion for others.

Moral education is an important part of any student’s education. It can help them become more responsible, compassionate and ethical individuals who are able to navigate the complexities of life with greater ease. In order to develop these qualities, students need to be exposed to a variety of moral theories and arguments. Moral education should not be limited to religious institutions; it should be available in all schools so that every student can benefit from it.

Paragraph Writing

Hello! Welcome to my Blog StudyParagraphs.co. My name is Angelina. I am a college professor. I love reading writing for kids students. This blog is full with valuable knowledge for all class students. Thank you for reading my articles.

Related Posts:

Paragraph on hard work is the to success

Leave a Reply Cancel reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *

Save my name, email, and website in this browser for the next time I comment.

The Student Daily

Career, Notifications & Jobs

Importance of Moral Education Essay

November 28, 2020 by Son of Ghouse Leave a Comment

In the modern era, when people around the world are civilized, we have an unprecedented boom in technology and science. Consequently, the quality and standard of life of the average person are at an all-time high. Though human history is comparatively newer on this 4.35 billion years old earth, we have managed to successfully hone the forces of nature to not just survive but thrive as a species. This write-up is an essay on importance of moral education essay.

Our ancestors started as hunters and gatherers, but now we are writing complex computer programs to make artificial intelligence carry out our space explorations. When you search for the reasons behind this huge evolution of human development, you can easily conclude that the system of education has made us more capable and competent.

Education is one of the most important processes that help an individual to be enlightened about his or her existence. Education provides us with knowledge in accessible and practical ways that guide future generations. This process provides an individual with skills, habits, beliefs, and values that will help him or her attain a successful and prosperous life.

There are various systems of education in different parts of the world. But no system of education can be complete without students getting proper moral education as a part of their curriculum.

Moral education consists of a set of beliefs and guidance acquired in the philosophical journey of our society. It makes a student well mannered, courteous, vigorous, non-bullying, obedient, and diligent. It guides the behavior, attitudes, and intentions of the students towards others and nature. It helps a person throughout his or her life to decide what is right or what is wrong.

Definition Of Moral Education

moral education essay questions

Some educational theories suggest that new avenues of the future can only open when the previous generation makes a path for it by staying out of the way. Though adults can take their moral understanding further with their ability of critical thinking that they acquire from systematic education, children require more careful attention as they are easily impressed and influenced. That is why the guidance of past generations and traditions remain very important in the form of moral education.

Moral education is very ambiguous as a term as different cultures, based on where they live and how they live, have a different set of moral values. But one thing that can be agreed upon universally is that moral education intends to shape the idea of ‘good’ and ‘bad’ in young minds.

By the term ‘good’, you can assimilate deeds like contributing towards a healthy society, not harming a fellow member of the society, helping others, being civic, and being productive. The term ‘bad’ however refers to any thought or force that opposes the good deeds.

Although the modern education system is very new and still developing, the branch of moral education has been taught to pupils since ancient times. Earlier, the duty of imparting moral lessons used to be carried out by the religious leaders and educators who specialized in uplifting the moral value of the society by both adhering to and reforming the old traditions. In the modern age, especially after the colonization of several parts of the world, moral education has been reinforced by the new age educationists.

In the contemporary world moral education has become more universal in approach. More and more humanitarian aspects like human rights, rights for specially-abled people, women’s rights, animal rights, and rights of other marginalized sections of the society have been included.

This progressive approach towards moral education results in a more harmonious society where students become more inclusive and compassionate towards each other along with being successful individually.

Also Read: Essay on Aatma nirbhar Bharat in English

Essay On Importance Of Moral Education In 150 Words

The purpose of an individual’s education is their all-round development, and not just securing high paying jobs, no matter how much the rat-races of the world may have convinced us otherwise.

The education of an individual can never be complete unless they have learned the lessons of tolerance, compassion, pluralistic values, respect, faith, honesty, and many other great virtues that are essential for an upright social life.

These lessons are acquired from the moral education that kids are imparted through stories, skits, interactions, dialogues,  and discourses, and are expected to come from the elder members of the society.

Moral lessons teach young children about ideas that take them towards the ‘good’ life and help them identify the ‘bad’. A life that is not guided by these lessons can easily go astray, and an individual leading such a life, instead of being useful and productive, turns out to be harmful to society.

Essay On Importance Of Moral Education In 250 Words

For a young student moral lessons are just as important as technical and scientific ones as these help in shaping their entire personality. The word moral comes from the Latin root ‘moris’ which means the code of conduct of a people, and the social adhesive that holds a community together.

Moral lessons teach students the importance of positive virtues like honesty, responsibility, mutual respect, helpfulness, kindness, and generosity, without which no society can ever function. At a personal level, this knowledge is essential for a healthy and meaningful life.

These lessons are also aimed at conveying the vital message that negative qualities like greed, vengeance, hatred, and violence can hinder the functioning of a productive society and can cause immense personal damage to the individual.

Since young minds are easily impressionable and assimilate both positive and negative influences easily, moral lessons are vital in helping them make righteous choices as adults. Moral education makes sure that children grow up to develop a virtuous character and lead a decent life.

History bears witness, whenever a society has deterred from the path of these moral values, calamities have befallen humankind. Had Adolf Hilter been taught the right lessons in tolerance and diversity, the world would have been spared the horrors of the Holocaust and a World War.

A proper system of moral education becomes instrumental in shaping the present and the future of a harmonious society. For the betterment of individuals and the community they live in, imparting the right values to children as students are therefore essential.

Essay On Importance Of Moral Education For Class 7&8

Moral education as a process of learning enables a child to acquire socially acceptable skills that make them a useful resource for society. In the present times, moral education is a necessity, keeping the changing systems of the world in mind.

Moral education should not begin in the confines of a classroom but should start in the comfort and security of a home. Parents should be the first idols of children from whom they learn the basics of moral conduct.

Imparting moral lessons to young kids who have just begun developing their thoughts and are yet to attain individuality is a task of great responsibility. They can only be shaped into righteous human beings if proper care and due guidance are provided.

It is to be remembered, in this relation, that kids learn more from observation and modeling than from lectures and discourses. The kind of environment they develop in and the kind of individuals they find as models play a vital role in shaping them as individuals.

It is, therefore, of utmost importance to make sure that children always find a healthy atmosphere of productivity and righteousness around them, with healthy, meaningful relationships with their parents and other elders.

However, when we allow kids to grow in an atmosphere of immoral conduct, we should only expect them to lead lives bereft of all morality. In such cases, the consequences can be dangerous.

A community whose children, the symbols of its future, develop without proper moral education is doomed to be submerged in the darkness of crimes, immorality, violence, hatred, discrimination, selfishness, and greed.

The benefits of moral education are numerous. Apart from teaching children socially useful values to guide their everyday life, an efficient system of moral education imparts lessons of cooperation. As a value, cooperation is not just vital to an individual’s everyday life, but also for the survival of human society.

There can be no future for human civilization if this value is left out of children’s education as we, as a society, need each other to survive. Morals of respect, love, compassion, kindness, forgiveness, and honesty help in imbibing this essential value among kids early on in life.

Moral education also helps in teaching children values of responsibility and independence which is otherwise difficult to make them learn. An effective curriculum of moral education would help children build a positive approach to difficult situations, and make them self confident. It helps children in realizing their purpose in life, their motivations, and goals, and make them dedicated to the cause of social well being.

Moral education is the only hope of humanity in the process of eradicating social evils like gender discrimination, animal abuse, oppression, violence, racial discrimination, and violence against minorities.

In order to create a better tomorrow and ascertain the continuation of human civilization, imparting moral education to children is a must. As an integral part of education as a whole, moral lessons should be focussed on, making sure that children receive an all-round education that enhances their personality.

Relevance Of Moral Education During The Present times

The present world is ever-changing. With the advent of technology and globalization, changes in family structure, the evolution of the education systems, changes in patterns of recreation, emergence of the ‘virtual’ world, and variations in the interpersonal relationships, children’s lives, thought patterns, and learning needs have undergone tremendous changes. Under these circumstances, the need and relevance of moral education have also changed.

With the virtual world casting a lasting impression on children, they have now become a lot more vulnerable to negative influences. Misuse of technology nowadays leads many young children and teenagers astray.

The damage caused in many cases is beyond repair. The distortions in the nature of human relationships and their consequences are having lasting impacts on young minds.

Under these changed circumstances, moral education has to assume a changed, and probably more important role. Due to the changes in most major spheres of life, moral values have also suffered major distortions.

Greed, violence, discrimination, and jealousy are becoming common among people. With social media, hatred spreads like wildfire. Values like honesty and generosity are only found in textbooks these days and their practical implications are becoming a rare sight.

Moral education is the only way in which the situation can be expected to improve. Proper moral education in classrooms and at home can help in boosting the morale of the students. But these lessons have to be provided in a more time-adjusted way to suit the need of the hour.

Making proper use of technology, a more visual and engaging curriculum can be drafted to engage the students in a practical and life-like manner.

Including moral education in school curriculums and adding extra weightage to these lessons is, therefore, a vital step to take in this direction.

As a society, the value of moral education is immense for us. If we are to produce sensible, kind, generous, responsible, and sensitized individuals to lead the future, moral education cannot be left out. In fact, our very existence as a civilization stands on how morally righteous and upright our future generations are.

Leave a Reply Cancel reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *

Save my name, email, and website in this browser for the next time I comment.

Read our research on: Gun Policy | International Conflict | Election 2024

Regions & Countries

3. problems students are facing at public k-12 schools.

We asked teachers about how students are doing at their school. Overall, many teachers hold negative views about students’ academic performance and behavior.

  • 48% say the academic performance of most students at their school is fair or poor; a third say it’s good and only 17% say it’s excellent or very good.
  • 49% say students’ behavior at their school is fair or poor; 35% say it’s good and 13% rate it as excellent or very good.

Teachers in elementary, middle and high schools give similar answers when asked about students’ academic performance. But when it comes to students’ behavior, elementary and middle school teachers are more likely than high school teachers to say it’s fair or poor (51% and 54%, respectively, vs. 43%).

A horizontal stacked bar chart showing that many teachers hold negative views about students’ academic performance and behavior.

Teachers from high-poverty schools are more likely than those in medium- and low-poverty schools to say the academic performance and behavior of most students at their school are fair or poor.

The differences between high- and low-poverty schools are particularly striking. Most teachers from high-poverty schools say the academic performance (73%) and behavior (64%) of most students at their school are fair or poor. Much smaller shares of teachers from low-poverty schools say the same (27% for academic performance and 37% for behavior).

In turn, teachers from low-poverty schools are far more likely than those from high-poverty schools to say the academic performance and behavior of most students at their school are excellent or very good.

Lasting impact of the COVID-19 pandemic

A horizontal stacked bar chart showing that most teachers say the pandemic has had a lasting negative impact on students’ behavior, academic performance and emotional well-being.

Among those who have been teaching for at least a year, about eight-in-ten teachers say the lasting impact of the pandemic on students’ behavior, academic performance and emotional well-being has been very or somewhat negative. This includes about a third or more saying that the lasting impact has been very negative in each area.

Shares ranging from 11% to 15% of teachers say the pandemic has had no lasting impact on these aspects of students’ lives, or that the impact has been neither positive nor negative. Only about 5% say that the pandemic has had a positive lasting impact on these things.

A smaller majority of teachers (55%) say the pandemic has had a negative impact on the way parents interact with teachers, with 18% saying its lasting impact has been very negative.

These results are mostly consistent across teachers of different grade levels and school poverty levels.

Major problems at school

When we asked teachers about a range of problems that may affect students who attend their school, the following issues top the list:

  • Poverty (53% say this is a major problem at their school)
  • Chronic absenteeism – that is, students missing a substantial number of school days (49%)
  • Anxiety and depression (48%)

One-in-five say bullying is a major problem among students at their school. Smaller shares of teachers point to drug use (14%), school fights (12%), alcohol use (4%) and gangs (3%).

Differences by school level

A bar chart showing that high school teachers more likely to say chronic absenteeism, anxiety and depression are major problems.

Similar shares of teachers across grade levels say poverty is a major problem at their school, but other problems are more common in middle or high schools:

  • 61% of high school teachers say chronic absenteeism is a major problem at their school, compared with 43% of elementary school teachers and 46% of middle school teachers.
  • 69% of high school teachers and 57% of middle school teachers say anxiety and depression are a major problem, compared with 29% of elementary school teachers.
  • 34% of middle school teachers say bullying is a major problem, compared with 13% of elementary school teachers and 21% of high school teachers.

Not surprisingly, drug use, school fights, alcohol use and gangs are more likely to be viewed as major problems by secondary school teachers than by those teaching in elementary schools.

Differences by poverty level

A dot plot showing that majorities of teachers in medium- and high-poverty schools say chronic absenteeism is a major problem.

Teachers’ views on problems students face at their school also vary by school poverty level.

Majorities of teachers in high- and medium-poverty schools say chronic absenteeism is a major problem where they teach (66% and 58%, respectively). A much smaller share of teachers in low-poverty schools say this (34%).

Bullying, school fights and gangs are viewed as major problems by larger shares of teachers in high-poverty schools than in medium- and low-poverty schools.

When it comes to anxiety and depression, a slightly larger share of teachers in low-poverty schools (51%) than in high-poverty schools (44%) say these are a major problem among students where they teach.  

Discipline practices

A pie chart showing that a majority of teachers say discipline practices at their school are mild.

About two-thirds of teachers (66%) say that the current discipline practices at their school are very or somewhat mild – including 27% who say they’re very mild. Only 2% say the discipline practices at their school are very or somewhat harsh, while 31% say they are neither harsh nor mild.

We also asked teachers about the amount of influence different groups have when it comes to determining discipline practices at their school.

  • 67% say teachers themselves don’t have enough influence. Very few (2%) say teachers have too much influence, and 29% say their influence is about right.

A diverging bar chart showing that two-thirds of teachers say they don’t have enough influence over discipline practices at their school.

  • 31% of teachers say school administrators don’t have enough influence, 22% say they have too much, and 45% say their influence is about right.
  • On balance, teachers are more likely to say parents, their state government and the local school board have too much influence rather than not enough influence in determining discipline practices at their school. Still, substantial shares say these groups have about the right amount of influence.

Teachers from low- and medium-poverty schools (46% each) are more likely than those in high-poverty schools (36%) to say parents have too much influence over discipline practices.

In turn, teachers from high-poverty schools (34%) are more likely than those from low- and medium-poverty schools (17% and 18%, respectively) to say that parents don’t have enough influence.

Social Trends Monthly Newsletter

Sign up to to receive a monthly digest of the Center's latest research on the attitudes and behaviors of Americans in key realms of daily life

Report Materials

Table of contents, ‘back to school’ means anytime from late july to after labor day, depending on where in the u.s. you live, among many u.s. children, reading for fun has become less common, federal data shows, most european students learn english in school, for u.s. teens today, summer means more schooling and less leisure time than in the past, about one-in-six u.s. teachers work second jobs – and not just in the summer, most popular.

About Pew Research Center Pew Research Center is a nonpartisan fact tank that informs the public about the issues, attitudes and trends shaping the world. It conducts public opinion polling, demographic research, media content analysis and other empirical social science research. Pew Research Center does not take policy positions. It is a subsidiary of The Pew Charitable Trusts .

moral education essay questions

Finished Papers

  • History Category
  • Psychology Category
  • Informative Category
  • Analysis Category
  • Business Category
  • Economics Category
  • Health Category
  • Literature Category
  • Review Category
  • Sociology Category
  • Technology Category

The various domains to be covered for my essay writing.

If you are looking for reliable and dedicated writing service professionals to write for you, who will increase the value of the entire draft, then you are at the right place. The writers of PenMyPaper have got a vast knowledge about various academic domains along with years of work experience in the field of academic writing. Thus, be it any kind of write-up, with multiple requirements to write with, the essay writer for me is sure to go beyond your expectations. Some most explored domains by them are:

  • Project management

Customer Reviews

Terms of Use

Privacy Policy

moral education essay questions

IMAGES

  1. Write a short essay on Moral Values

    moral education essay questions

  2. Moral education essay in English || Moral education par English essay

    moral education essay questions

  3. Argumentative essay: Essay on importance of moral education

    moral education essay questions

  4. Class 8 Moral Education Question Paper

    moral education essay questions

  5. Write a short essay on Need For Moral Education

    moral education essay questions

  6. Importance of Moral Science in School Essay Example

    moral education essay questions

VIDEO

  1. todays exam : question paper review sem 3 and 5 #educareliveonquestionpaper

  2. An Essay on Education

  3. Online Education

  4. importance of education essay

  5. 10 lines about Education

  6. Co-Education Essay Quotes || Co-Education Essay For 2nd Year Quotations || City Academy MG

COMMENTS

  1. Moral Education Essays: Examples, Topics, & Outlines

    WORDS 445. Outline: The Complexity of Human Nature. I. Introduction. A. Hook: Begin with a thought-provoking question or anecdote that highlights the enigma of human nature. B. Thesis statement: State the central argument that humans are multifaceted beings with both noble and darker impulses. II.

  2. 19 questions with answers in MORAL EDUCATION

    1. Inculcating is contradictory to academic education, as it can hinder the free development of ideas and concepts. 2. Nevertheless, students should be aware of some elementary ethics that play a ...

  3. What Is "Moral Education"?

    Moral education is one of the central concerns of philosophy of education. Over the years, it has been described using a variety of terms—"moral education", "values education", "ethics and education" and "character education". Ultimately, these diverse appellations all focus on the question of "What is the role of education ...

  4. Defining Moral Education

    One task for moral education in the modern college or university, then, is to articulate and scrutinize the moral ends of our shared enterprise. Truth seeking, a willingness to think deeply about alternative positions and arguments, to be swayed by evidence and argument, to acknowledge our intellectual debts to others, and to judge others on ...

  5. Moral Values in Education

    Moral Values in Education Essay. The responsibility of educating a child falls on both the parents and the teachers. In most instances, teachers are always trying to get the parents to be part of their children's education. On the other hand, parents tend to handle any communication from their children's teachers delicately.

  6. Moral sensitivity: The central question of moral education

    Moral relativism gains no support from the fact that we all inherit a cultural tradition—succinctly defined by Kekes as 'the network of a certain sort of customary conduct that exists in society', and by reference to which moral education may be said to be an 'initiation into the vision and possibilities in human life [or] a training in the development of a sensibility in terms of ...

  7. Moral Education in the 21st Century

    Kristján Kristjánsson - University of Birmingham, UK, and Editor, Journal of Moral Education 'Together, these essays position moral education at the heart of human existence, invigorating our sense of what is at stake in the aspiration to behave better in day-to-day and collective life. ... It covers an ambitious breadth of topics while not ...

  8. Moral Education Essay

    The Importance Of Moral Education. focuses on children, and their moral education. A moral education encompasses what children need to be taught including right and wrong. A moral education consisted of ethics and morals. Morals included personal character, and ethics put morales to the test . What happens if a parent does not do their job of ...

  9. Duke University Press

    The essays quickly open up to broader questions regarding the very purpose of a university education in modern society. Editors Elizabeth Kiss and J. Peter Euben survey the history of ethics in higher education, then engage with provocative recent writings by Stanley Fish in which he argues that universities should not be involved in moral ...

  10. An introduction to the special issue on wisdom and moral education

    questions of moral development and education. Under the general umbrella of 'wisdom' there lurk a number of sub-concepts. Two of those can, arguably, be defined with reasonable specificity. One is wisdom as sophia: excellence in contemplating the topics of some of the most abstract subjects of study, such as mathematics and physics (and

  11. 99 Moral Development Essay Topic Ideas & Examples

    Kohlberg's Stages of Moral Development in Justice System. Burglars, whose predominant level of morality is conventional, tend to consider the opinion of the society on their actions. Kohlberg's stages of moral development help to identify the problems and find solutions to them. Moral Development and Aggression.

  12. Moral Education

    1.3 Moral Conduct. Moral education concerns proper ways to act toward other people and, in some cultures, proper ways to act toward supernatural forces (gods, ancestral spirits), nonhuman beings (animals of specified types), and physical surroundings (sacred forests, mountains, and waterways). All cultures teach such virtues as honesty, loyalty ...

  13. The Importance Of Moral Education

    700 Words. 3 Pages. Open Document. Understanding what society believes is morally correct and incorrect can determine the success of developing youth. Moral education can improve students' decision-making skills and nurture the virtues and values within them. If children abide by incorrect morals, they run the risk of underage drinking or ...

  14. Moral Disagreement and Moral Education: What's the Problem?

    Although initially plausible, the view that moral education should aim at the transmission of moral knowledge has been subject to severe criticism. In this context, one particularly prominent line of argumentation rests on the empirical observation that moral questions are subject to widespread and robust disagreement. In this paper, I would like to discuss the implications of moral ...

  15. 180 Ethics Topics & Ethical Questions to Debate

    180 Ethics Topics & Ethical Questions to Debate. (31 votes) Our code of ethics is derived from what we think is right or wrong. On top of that, we have to agree to the moral standards established by the society we live in. Conventional norms generally label theft, murder, or harassment as bad. However, there are many influences that impact our ...

  16. Importance of Moral Education Essay For Students

    Moral education is essential for students to have in order to create good, ethical citizens. It teaches students about right and wrong, values, and the responsibilities that come with having those values. It also helps students make informed decisions and handle difficult situations. Moral education should start early in a student's life.

  17. Moral Education Essays

    the moral education theory. First, in the moral view of education, the state is concerned to educate its citizens morally so they will not choose the wrong behavior (Hampton, 276). Secondly, the criminal is not to be used for social engineering (Hampton, 276). The second point is important.

  18. Moral Values Essay

    Long Essay on Moral Values 500 Words. The long essay on moral values is for students belonging to classes 6,7,8,9, and 10, and competitive exam aspirants. The essay is a guide to help with class assignments, comprehension, and competitive examinations. Society disseminates values, religion, culture, politics, and economy in an individual.

  19. Importance of Moral Education Essay

    Moral education consists of a set of beliefs and guidance acquired in the philosophical journey of our society. It makes a student well mannered, courteous, vigorous, non-bullying, obedient, and diligent. It guides the behavior, attitudes, and intentions of the students towards others and nature. It helps a person throughout his or her life to ...

  20. ME Revision Booklet 1 March 21

    Examination Paper Structure Moral Education examinations consist of two papers as outlined below: Paper 1: Consists of 40 Multiple Choice Questions and it is marked out of 40. The duration of this paper is 1 hour and it carries 40% of all the marks in the JCE ME Course.

  21. PDF MORAL EDUCATION ASSESSMENT SYLLABUS

    2.3 analyse morality of citizenship, economic, social and political issues; 2.4 analyse morality of new emerging issues. 4. Scheme of Assessment. The JCE Moral Education syllabus will be assessed through a Multiple-Choice paper and a written paper. Paper 1. Multiple-Choice. Time. 1 hour.

  22. 3. Problems students are facing at public K-12 schools

    Major problems at school. When we asked teachers about a range of problems that may affect students who attend their school, the following issues top the list: Poverty (53% say this is a major problem at their school) Chronic absenteeism - that is, students missing a substantial number of school days (49%) Anxiety and depression (48%) One-in ...

  23. Moral Education Essay Questions

    Moral Education Essay Questions. The narration in my narrative work needs to be smooth and appealing to the readers while writing my essay. Our writers enhance the elements in the writing as per the demand of such a narrative piece that interests the readers and urges them to read along with the entire writing.

  24. Moral Education Essay Questions

    Moral Education Essay Questions. Meet Eveline! Her commitment to quality surprises both the students and fellow team members. Eveline never stops until you're 100% satisfied with the result. She believes essay writing to be her specialty. Visit the order page and download the assignment file.

  25. Teens are spending nearly 5 hours daily on social media. Here are the

    41%. Percentage of teens with the highest social media use who rate their overall mental health as poor or very poor, compared with 23% of those with the lowest use. For example, 10% of the highest use group expressed suicidal intent or self-harm in the past 12 months compared with 5% of the lowest use group, and 17% of the highest users expressed poor body image compared with 6% of the lowest ...